13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

mathematics and physics: strategies <strong>of</strong> assimilation 421disturb this basic picture, since, although category theory does in fact providea more convenient framework than set theory in many cases, there are somegeneral techniques available for reconciling category-theoretic methods withthose <strong>of</strong> set theory (Blass, 1984).One does not have to go far in the literature <strong>of</strong> physics to discover that nosuch consensus on the notion <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> exists in that area. Work in physics runsthe gamut from fully rigorous pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> theorems (most <strong>of</strong> the literature ingeneral relativity falls into this category) to purely formal manipulations backedup by computer simulations, as in the case <strong>of</strong> a large part <strong>of</strong> the literaturein condensed matter physics. The important area <strong>of</strong> quantum field theoryoccupies a kind <strong>of</strong> intermediate position, where some <strong>of</strong> the computationscan be made fully rigorous, as a result <strong>of</strong> the hard work <strong>of</strong> constructive fieldtheorists (Glimm and Jaffe, 1987; Johnson and Lapidus, 2000), whereas thecomputations that really matter to the physicists, such as those in quantumelectrodynamics and quantum chromodynamics, still seem to languish in amathematical limbo, being defined only in terms <strong>of</strong> ill-defined perturbationexpansions about the theory <strong>of</strong> the free field.The number <strong>of</strong> physicists who write papers that satisfy the usual standards<strong>of</strong> mathematical rigour is small, perhaps only a few per cent <strong>of</strong> the total number<strong>of</strong> working physicists. However, their work is among the great achievements <strong>of</strong>the physics <strong>of</strong> the last century. I might mention here the work <strong>of</strong> Lars Onsageron the two-dimensional Ising model, and that <strong>of</strong> Dyson, Lieb, and Thirringon the stability <strong>of</strong> matter. These are examples <strong>of</strong> beautiful mathematics as wellas beautiful physics, and it is purely a historical accident that this work is notusually considered among the major mathematical accomplishments <strong>of</strong> the lastcentury.It is easy to understand that classically trained mathematicians might regardwith horror this unruly world <strong>of</strong> purely formal computations, in which itis hard to lay hold <strong>of</strong> mathematical bedrock in the maelstrom <strong>of</strong> ill-definedinfinite series and objects whose nature is far from clear. The mathematicianYuri Manin conveys this bewilderment very tellingly:The author, by training a mathematician, once delivered four lectures to studentsunder the title ‘How a mathematician should study physics’. In the lectures he saidthat modern theoretical physics is a luxuriant, totally Rabelaisian, vigorous world<strong>of</strong> ideas, and a mathematician can find in it everything to satiate himself exceptthe order to which he is accustomed. Therefore a good method for attuningoneself to the active study <strong>of</strong> physics is to pretend that you are attempting toinduce this very order in it. (Manin, 1981, p.x)The remainder <strong>of</strong> this article will be devoted to the topic <strong>of</strong> just howmathematicians attempt to induce this order.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!