13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

84 kenneth mandersirrelevant, unable to provide its participants a non-trivial grip on life: whateverparticipants have to go on in the game must support distinctions where differentactions are required.If the only response ever required to p 1 and p 2 is q, we could disregardthe difference between p 1 and p 2 ,alwayswritep 1 ,oralwayswritep. Butparticipants typically can’t assess ‘only response ever required’, nor—here ourschematic p 1 , p 2 notation breaks down—can they typically assess what range<strong>of</strong> alternatives might ultimately be relevant. In its diagram use, Euclideangeometry ‘writes p 1 ’ until it becomes clear some ‘p ′ ’ could require a differentresponse. A diagram adequate at one stage <strong>of</strong> a pro<strong>of</strong> may upon developmentbe ‘un-representative’; this forces a case distinction in which multiple diagramsare considered separately. The peculiar success <strong>of</strong> various later geometries restsnot only on their surprising reduction <strong>of</strong> diversity in artifact and response, butalso on the way the correlative collapse <strong>of</strong> ranges <strong>of</strong> alternatives, quite as aby-product, <strong>of</strong>ten eliminates imponderables that participants in diagram-basedgeometry cannot count on being able to assess.The way its artifacts lie in the game is not innocent to the control its playerscan achieve.4.1.2 Diagrams and semantic roleArtifacts in a practice that gives us a grip on life are sometimes thought <strong>of</strong> insemantic terms—say, as representing something in life. There is, <strong>of</strong> course, anage-old debate on how geometrical diagrams are to be treated in this regard.Long-standing philosophical difficulties, on the nature <strong>of</strong> geometric objectsand our knowledge <strong>of</strong> them, arise from the assumption that the geometricaltext is in an ordinary sense true <strong>of</strong> the diagram or a ‘perfect counterpart’. Thesedifficulties aside, a genuinely semantic relationship between the geometricaldiagram and text is incompatible with the successful use <strong>of</strong> diagrams in pro<strong>of</strong> bycontradiction: reductio contexts serve precisely to assemble a body <strong>of</strong> assertionswhich patently could not together be true; hence no genuine geometricalsituation could in a serious sense be pictured in which they were.¹ Thissimple-minded objection has nothing to do specifically with geometry: pro<strong>of</strong>sby contradiction never admit <strong>of</strong> semantics in which each entry in the pro<strong>of</strong>sequence is true (in any sense which entails their joint compatibility).To help be a bit more precise: I take it that among logical formalisms, naturaldeduction systems reconstruct most directly the actual patterns <strong>of</strong> occurrence¹ David Sherry has directed this argument at Berkeley’s conception <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> diagrams, anddraws a similar conclusion (Sherry, 1993, p.214). But Sherry makes only incidental proposals on howdiagrams support inferences (p. 217) and expects to invoke Pasch-style axioms (n. 5).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!