13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

understanding pro<strong>of</strong>s 34912.9 Understanding numeric substructuresAs a fourth and final example, I would like to consider a class <strong>of</strong> inferencesthat involve reasoning about the domains <strong>of</strong> natural numbers, integers, rationalnumbers, real numbers, and complex numbers, with respect to one another.From a foundational perspective, it is common to take the natural numbers asbasic, or to construct them from even more basic objects, like sets. Integerscan then be viewed as equivalence classes <strong>of</strong> pairs <strong>of</strong> natural numbers; rationalnumbers can be viewed as equivalence classes <strong>of</strong> pairs <strong>of</strong> integers; real numberscan be viewed, say, as sequences <strong>of</strong> rational numbers; and complex numberscan be viewed as pairs <strong>of</strong> reals. As McLarty points out in the first <strong>of</strong> his essaysin this collection, however, this puts us in a funny situation. After all, wethink <strong>of</strong> the natural numbers as a subset <strong>of</strong> the integers, the integers as a subset<strong>of</strong> the rationals, and so on. On the foundational story, this is not quite true;really, each domain is embedded in the larger ones. Of course, once we havethe complex numbers, we may choose to baptize the complex image <strong>of</strong> ouroriginal copy <strong>of</strong> the natural numbers as our new working version. Even if wedo this, however, we still have to keep track <strong>of</strong> where individual elements‘live’. For example, we can apply the principle <strong>of</strong> induction to the complexcopy <strong>of</strong> the natural numbers, but not to the complex numbers as a whole;and we can divide one natural number by another, but the result may notbe a natural number. If we think <strong>of</strong> the natural numbers as embedded inthe complex numbers, we have to use an embedding function to make ourstatements literally true; if we think <strong>of</strong> them as being a subset <strong>of</strong> the complexnumbers, all <strong>of</strong> our statements have to be carefully qualified so that we havespecified what types <strong>of</strong> objects we are dealing with.The funny thing is that in ordinary mathematical texts, all this happens underthe surface. Textbooks almost never tell us which <strong>of</strong> these two foundationaloptions are being followed, because the choice has no effect on the subsequentarguments. And when we read a theorem that combines the different domains,we somehow manage to interpret the statements in such a way that everythingmakes sense. For example, you probably did not think twice about the factthat Lemma 1 above involved three sorts <strong>of</strong> number domain. The fact that theseries is indexed by n means that we have to think <strong>of</strong> n as a natural number(or a positive integer). Similarly, there is an implicit indexing <strong>of</strong> terms bynatural numbers in the use <strong>of</strong> ‘ ... ’ in the expression for the logarithm. Thepro<strong>of</strong>, in fact, made use <strong>of</strong> properties <strong>of</strong> such sums that are typically provedby induction. In the statement <strong>of</strong> the theorem, the variable z is explicitlydesignated to denote a complex number, so when we divide z by n in the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!