13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

72 kenneth manders3.2 Geometric generalityA traditional quandary about geometrical demonstration, famously discussedby Locke, Berkeley, and Kant, is how one particular drawn diagram can justifya general claim.1. Some20th century commentaries on geometrical generality may missthe mark because our ‘strict-universal’ standards for universal quantification,by including singular (in the mathematical sense) instances, disagree withtraditional mathematical usage.A traditional geometrical demonstration only claims to establish its propositionfor non-trivial instances <strong>of</strong> its initial diagram, in which items such as anglesand triangles contain proper regions (respecting the co-exact component <strong>of</strong>these notions, explained above). The demonstration <strong>of</strong> I.1, for example, doesnot purport to construct an equilateral triangle on a ‘side’ consisting <strong>of</strong> a singlepoint. Individuating claims in this way is rational: as the example suggests,direct argument for (analogs <strong>of</strong>) claims in such limiting cases tends to be mucheasier than the demonstration at hand.Perhaps because later algebraic and calculus methods establish (most) limitingcases automatically, non-triviality understandings on primitive geometricnotions eventually vanished. From this later point <strong>of</strong> view, singular situationsbecame ‘exceptions’; traditional general claims and arguments have the force <strong>of</strong>‘admitting’ exceptions, i.e. not applying to certain singular instances.Strict-universal usage is surprisingly recent: ‘The subject treated ... illustrateswell one <strong>of</strong> the most striking tendencies <strong>of</strong> modern algebraic and analyticwork, namely, the tendency not to be satisfied with results that are merelytrue ‘‘in general’’, i.e. with more or less numerous exceptions, but to strivefor theorems which are always true.’ ‘The great importance <strong>of</strong> this tendencywill be apparent if we remember that when we apply a theorem, it is usuallyto a special case. If we merely know that it is true ‘‘in general’’, we mustfirst consider whether the special case ... is not one <strong>of</strong> the exceptional cases inwhich the theorem fails.’ (Bôcher (1901)) For the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> theorems‘with exception’, see also Sorensen (2005).2. Whether particular drawn diagrams suffice to justify general geometricalclaims (in the sense just recovered) depends on how demonstrations usediagrams. Particularity is not an incurable infectious agent.Beth (1956) suggested, and Hintikka developed, the idea that the setting-out<strong>of</strong> the diagram in ancient demonstration be understood by analogy to thesetting-aside <strong>of</strong> letters in universal generalization (UG) rules in modern logic,say as opening a scope for UG in a natural deduction system. But does analogy

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!