13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

purity <strong>of</strong> method in hilbert’s grundlagen 215formulation <strong>of</strong> the congruence axioms. Linear congruence in geometry, boththe idea <strong>of</strong> congruence, and the central propositions governing it, was originallymotivated by simple observations about movement <strong>of</strong> rigid bodies in space,but Hilbert’s axioms are no longer to do with movement itself, though theconnection between them and the movement <strong>of</strong> rigid bodies is not hard todiscern. Rather, Hilbert’s view (see Hilbert, ∗ 1899, pp. 59–60) is that a propermathematical analysis <strong>of</strong> spatial movement requires an independently establishedand neutral notion <strong>of</strong> congruence. Thus the abstract notions are to be appliedin the analysis <strong>of</strong> movement, but geometry with Hilbert’s congruence axiomsis not dependent upon the purely empirical matter <strong>of</strong> whether or not thereare in fact rigid bodies, and thus whether bodies can indeed ever be congruentin the intuitive sense. In pursuing mathematical investigations <strong>of</strong> geometry,one is investigating ‘possible forms <strong>of</strong> connection’ and not necessarily ‘actualconnections’, an emancipation which reflects the ascent to what Hilbert callsthe conceptual.It follows from this account that even if the underlying notion <strong>of</strong> intuitionwere strong enough to guarantee the ‘apodeictic certainty’ <strong>of</strong> the axioms, itwould still be possible to drop axioms, or modify them, or replace them, and itwould still be part <strong>of</strong> the task <strong>of</strong> mathematics to investigate the consequences<strong>of</strong> so doing. In other words, a strong notion <strong>of</strong> intuition would not restrainHilbert’s axiomatic programme.There is another important consequence <strong>of</strong> this, namely that theoriescannot be straightforwardly true or false through correctly representing somefixed subject matter, or failing to represent it. This is stated clearly in the1922/1923 lectures, but it is already clear in the 1898/1899 lectures and the1899 correspondence with Frege. Theories, variously interpretable, are either‘possible’ or not, and what shows their ‘possibility’ is a demonstration <strong>of</strong>consistency, in which case the mathematical theory ‘exists’. Thus, for Hilbert,the correct account <strong>of</strong> truth and falsity with respect to mathematical theoriesis that <strong>of</strong> consistency/inconsistency. Derivatively a mathematical object exists(relative to the theory) if an appropriate existence statement can be derivedwithin the consistent theory. As Hilbert puts it in his 1919 lectures:What however is meant here by existence? If one looks more closely, one findsthat when one speaks <strong>of</strong> existence, it is always meant with respect to a definitesystem taken as given, and indeed this system is different, according to the theorywhich we are dealing with. (Hilbert, 1919, p.147, book p. 90).Hilbert sums this up in his 1902 lectures on the foundations <strong>of</strong> geometry:We must now show the freedom from contradiction <strong>of</strong> these axioms taken together;... .In order to facilitate the understanding <strong>of</strong> this, we begin with a remark:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!