13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

414 alasdair urquhartAt least two strategies can be observed in the process <strong>of</strong> absorbing physicalideas into the fabric <strong>of</strong> mathematics. One is to treat the ideas <strong>of</strong> the physicistsas purely heuristic in nature, and to establish their mathematical conjectures byconventional means. A second and more radical idea is to attempt to reworkthe ideas <strong>of</strong> the physicists and thereby construct new conceptual schemes thatvalidate at least some <strong>of</strong> their calculations. It is this second idea towards whichDyson points in the quotation above. In the research contribution followingthis introductory chapter, I shall discuss a number <strong>of</strong> relevant cases from thehistory <strong>of</strong> mathematics, as well as mentioning some open areas where thisprocess <strong>of</strong> mathematical assimilation is still fragmentary or incomplete.15.4 Further readingThe topic <strong>of</strong> the interaction between mathematics and physics is vast, and thischapter discusses only a single aspect <strong>of</strong> this interaction. In §15.1, mean fieldmodels were discussed as examples <strong>of</strong> models in physics that seem to contradictolder received views on scientific explanation. The book by Robert W.Batterman (2002) contains detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> many other models <strong>of</strong> asimilar type. He points out (Batterman, 2002,p.13) that science <strong>of</strong>ten requiresmethods that ‘eliminate both detail, and, in some sense, precision’. He describessuch methods as ‘asymptotic methods’, and the type <strong>of</strong> reasoning involved inthem as ‘asymptotic reasoning’. He draws very interesting and rather heterodoxconclusions from this fact concerning models <strong>of</strong> scientific explanation andtheory reduction, as well as the notion <strong>of</strong> emergent properties. (See alsothe very interesting review Belot (2005) and the reply by Batterman (2005).)Similar themes in the context <strong>of</strong> condensed matter physics are discussed in theunusually stimulating monograph by Martin H. Krieger (1996).In the conclusion to a widely cited essay John von Neumann (1947) wrote:At a great distance from its empirical source, or after much ‘abstract’ inbreeding,a mathematical subject is in danger <strong>of</strong> degeneration. At the inception the style isusually classical; when it shows signs <strong>of</strong> becoming baroque, then the danger signalis up. ... Whenever this stage is reached, the only remedy seems to me to be therejuvenating return to the source: the reinjection <strong>of</strong> more or less empirical ideas.I am convinced that this was a necessary condition to conserve the freshness andthe vitality <strong>of</strong> the subject and that this will remain equally true in the future.Mathematics is now in the midst <strong>of</strong> a period <strong>of</strong> rapid growth throughthe absorption <strong>of</strong> a multitude <strong>of</strong> new ideas from physics. This renewedinteraction between the two fields <strong>of</strong>fers, in addition to the problems already

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!