13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 131grasp <strong>of</strong> its construction) provides some control over what is an appropriatechallenge, this control is singularly inarticulate.The claims and arguments which might be appropriate to the situationprobed may be felt to address a variety <strong>of</strong> questions, which might or might nothave appeared inarticulately bound up in the original sensation <strong>of</strong> impotence:when the diagram showed what it did, (i) could that have been a breakdown <strong>of</strong>appearance control? (ii) What might have been relevant about the free metricchoices: can we identify features or ranges <strong>of</strong> these choices that demonstrablylead to the outcome appearance? (iii) What other appearances might arise fromdifferent metric choices? (iv) What is the range <strong>of</strong> control possibilities andoutcomes?When we have achieved a favorable resolution, acquired a measure <strong>of</strong>enhanced intellectual control over the original diagram occurrence, we maychoose to characterize the enhancement as the acquisition <strong>of</strong> one or more <strong>of</strong>several broad virtues: we may say we have justified a claim about the outcome,or that we have explained why the construction gave the outcome, or that wehave articulated claims, conditions, reasons, arguments...The responsibility for geometrical claims that comes with being a geometeris thus much broader than a concern for reliability. Probing, too, should now beseen as far more than an element <strong>of</strong> criticism in an overall justificational strategy.Probing is the form <strong>of</strong> action within geometrical practice through whichparticipants undertake their responsibility to improve its overall intellectualstanding. Presumably, such a conception is not special to geometry, but insteadcommon to a range <strong>of</strong> intellectual practices.We tend to fail to recognize probing at work, fail to apply the concept—asit were, miss its unity—in two distinct ways. We can be distracted bythe diverseness or special character <strong>of</strong> probing actions in particular situations;as when we are tempted to distinguish case and objection by who canconveniently respond. Or we can be distracted by the diverseness or specialcharacter <strong>of</strong> evaluations that drive probing or praise its accomplishments inparticular situations; as when we take formal pro<strong>of</strong>s in Tarski’s system tosettle justificational issues while asserting that they, taken by themselves, aregeometrically unintelligible.We can learn much, perhaps, by making such discriminations among actiontypes and among evaluation types, in contexts where those distinctions areviable. It is important, however, to insist on the unity <strong>of</strong> probing overthese two multiplicities because they are incompatible: varieties <strong>of</strong> probingactions do not match up with varieties <strong>of</strong> intellectual virtues that arise fromthem. Case proposal does not go with justification while objection goes withexplanation, or vice versa. Probing the two-circle intersection construction by

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!