13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

introduction 19in metaphyics when discussing fruitfulness and naturalness <strong>of</strong> concepts; andMacLarty shows how structuralism in mathematical practice can help usevaluate structuralist philosophies <strong>of</strong> mathematics. Indeed, the whole book isan attempt to expand the boundaries <strong>of</strong> epistemology <strong>of</strong> mathematics wellbeyond the problem <strong>of</strong> how we can have access to abstract entities.But coming now to the analytic developments related to Maddy’s work,I should point out that whereas Maddy has limited her investigations to settheory we take a much wider perspective on mathematical practice, drawingour case studies from geometry, complex analysis, real algebraic geometry,category theory, computer science, and mathematical physics. Once again, webelieve that while set theory is a very important subject <strong>of</strong> methodologicalinvestigation, there are central phenomena that will be missed unless wecast our net more broadly and extend our investigations to other areas <strong>of</strong>mathematics. Moreover, while Maddy’s study <strong>of</strong> set-theoretic methodologyhas some points <strong>of</strong> contact with our investigations (evidence, fruitfulness,theory-choice) we look at a much broader set <strong>of</strong> issues that never comeup for discussion in her work (visualization, purity <strong>of</strong> methods, explanation,rigor in mathematical physics). The closest point <strong>of</strong> contact between herinvestigations and this book is probably the discussion <strong>of</strong> evidence in Avigad’sintroduction. There is also no explicit commitment in our contributions tothe form <strong>of</strong> mathematical naturalism advocated by Maddy; actually, the spirit<strong>of</strong> many <strong>of</strong> our contributions seems to go against the grain <strong>of</strong> her philosophicalposition.Let me conclude by coming back to the comparison with the situation inphilosophy <strong>of</strong> science. I mentioned at the beginning that recent philosophy<strong>of</strong> science has thrived under the interaction <strong>of</strong> traditional problems (realismvs. instrumentalism, causality, etc.) with more localized studies in the philosophies<strong>of</strong> the special sciences. In general, philosophers <strong>of</strong> science are happy withclaiming that both areas are vital for the discipline. Corfield takes as the modelfor his approach to the philosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics the localized studies in thephilosophy <strong>of</strong> physics, but decrees that classical philosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematicsis a useless pursuit (see Pincock (2005)). As for Maddy, she gets away fromtraditional ontological and epistemological issues (realism, nominalism, etc.)by means <strong>of</strong> her naturalism. What is distinctive in this volume is that weintegrate local studies with general philosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics, contra Corfield,and we also keep traditional ontological and epistemological topics in play,contra Maddy.Hopefully, the reader will realize that my aim has not been to make anyinvidious comparisons but only to provide a fair account <strong>of</strong> what the previoustraditions have achieved and why we think we have achieved something worth

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!