13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

366 colin mclarty1930s (Washington, 1997, p.101). This could eliminate Galois cohomologyfrom the pro<strong>of</strong> but Washington takes it the other way around as introducingthat cohomology to the reader. The elimination would be routine and wouldreplace conceptual arguments by opaque calculations. Of course, to shortcutWiles’s use <strong>of</strong> cohomology by genuinely simpler new insights would bewonderful—like shortening any pro<strong>of</strong> by any simpler new insight.13.3.3 LanguagesSome philosophical theories <strong>of</strong> structuralism allow ‘no intelligible attempt—<strong>of</strong>the kind that Zermelo and Fraenkel undertook—to unify mathematical practice’(MacBride, 2005, p.572). Structural methods in practice, though, standout for making the unity <strong>of</strong> mathematics work more deeply and powerfullythan Zermelo and Fraenkel ever did. Barry Mazur well expressed this inaccepting the 2000 Steele Prize. He names the founders <strong>of</strong> category theoryEilenberg, Mac Lane, and Grothendieck, not for category theory but also notby coincidence. He names them for what they did with the theory:I came to number theory through the route <strong>of</strong> algebraic geometry and beforethat, topology. The unifying spirit at work in those subjects gave all the newideas a resonance and buoyancy which allowed them to instantly echo elsewhere,inspiring analogies in other branches and inspiring more ideas. One has only tothink <strong>of</strong> how the work <strong>of</strong> Eilenberg, Mac Lane, Steenrod, and Thom in topologyand the early work in class field theory as further developed in the hands <strong>of</strong>Emil Artin, Tate, and Iwasawa was unified and amplified in the point <strong>of</strong> view<strong>of</strong> algebraic geometry adopted by Grothendieck, a point <strong>of</strong> view inspired bythe Weil conjectures, which presaged the inextricable bond between topologyand arithmetic. One has only to think <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Serre or <strong>of</strong> Tate.¹⁶But mathematics is one subject, and surely every part <strong>of</strong> mathematics has beenenriched by ideas from other parts. (NAMS, 2000, p.479)These methods cultivate each branch <strong>of</strong> mathematics in its own terms, andhighlight how each one precisely in its own terms has bonds to others.Poincaré defended geometry and specifically his beloved analysis situs nowcalled topology against those who would reduce all mathematics to differentialanalysis. We must not ‘fail to recognize the importance <strong>of</strong> well constructedlanguage’:The problems <strong>of</strong> analysis situs might not have suggested themselves if the analyticlanguage alone had been spoken; or, rather, I am mistaken, they would haveoccurred surely, since their solution is essential to a crowd <strong>of</strong> questions in analysis.¹⁶ See references to Artin, Iwasawa, Tate, and Thom in Monastyrsky (1998). Serre and the Weilconjectures are central to the accompanying case study.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!