13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

eyond unification 173E I (K) comes out as the best systematization <strong>of</strong> K on Kitcher’s model, aspointed out above, contrary to how it is considered from the perspective <strong>of</strong>actual mathematical practice. This reveals a serious defect <strong>of</strong> Kitcher’s model.Against this result one may object as follows. The account <strong>of</strong> Kitcher’smodel on which our ranking <strong>of</strong> E I (K) is based leaves out completely thestringency criterion. Yet, the argument pattern TSP has exactly the same flawas the trivial argument patterns considered—and rejected—above. It allowsany vocabulary whatever (from the language <strong>of</strong> ordered fields) to appear inthe place <strong>of</strong> ‘ϕ’ and‘ψ’. Hence it, too, should be rejected as non-stringent.In other words, taking into account the stringency criterion not only blocksE I (K) from being ranked higher than E II (K) and E III (K) but it even excludesE I (K) altogether from the ‘competition’ as an inadmissible, spurious unification.Hence it poses no threat to Kitcher’s model after all.To see how much weight this objection indeed carries we have to evaluateit not at the level <strong>of</strong> our intuitive concept <strong>of</strong> stringency but in light <strong>of</strong> theexplicit requirement Kitcher formulates to screen out spurious unifications.If the filling instructions associated with a pattern P could be replaced by differentfilling instructions, allowing for the substitution <strong>of</strong> a class <strong>of</strong> expressions <strong>of</strong> thesame syntactic category, to yield a pattern P ′ and if P ′ would allow the derivation<strong>of</strong> any sentence, then the unification achieved by P is spurious. (Kitcher, 1981,p. 527f)This requirement in fact identifies as spurious the previously consideredtrivial argument patterns since the filling instruction ‘α’ istobereplacedby any sentence we accept’ can be generalized to ‘α’ istobereplacedbyany sentence’ thus allowing the derivation <strong>of</strong> any sentence. Kitcher furtherillustrates and motivates his new requirement with respect to the followingargument pattern which might be used by ‘a group <strong>of</strong> religious fanatics’ toexplain and unify their beliefs about the world (cf. Kitcher, 1981, p.528).(1) God wants it to be the case that α.(2) What God wants to be the case is the case.(3) αFilling instruction: ‘α’ is to be replaced by any sentence describing thephysical world.This pattern is also identified by the new requirement as spurious since itcan be trivialized by changing the filling instruction to ‘α’ istobereplacedbyany sentence’. And Kitcher continues:Why should patterns whose filling instructions can be modified to accommodateany sentence be suspect? The answer is that, in such patterns, the nonlogical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!