13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

26 marcus giaquintoMiller himself has surely gone through exactly the kind <strong>of</strong> process describedabove. Of course the actual event would have been split up in time, and Millerwould have already known the conclusion to be true; still, the whole thingwould have been a case <strong>of</strong> thinking through a pro<strong>of</strong>, a highly untypical case <strong>of</strong>course, in which visual thinking occurred in a non-superfluous way.This is enough to refute claim (a), the claim that all diagrammatic thinkingin thinking through a pro<strong>of</strong> is superfluous. What about Tennant’s claim that apro<strong>of</strong> is ‘a syntactic object consisting only <strong>of</strong> sentences’ as opposed to diagrams?A pro<strong>of</strong> is never a syntactic object. A formal derivation on its own is a syntacticobject but not a pro<strong>of</strong>. Without an interpretation <strong>of</strong> the language <strong>of</strong> theformal system the end-formula <strong>of</strong> the derivation says nothing; and so nothingis proved. Without a demonstration <strong>of</strong> the system’s soundness with respectto the interpretation, one lacks reason to believe that derived conclusions aretrue. A formal derivation plus an interpretation and soundness pro<strong>of</strong> can be apro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the derived conclusion. But one and the same soundness pro<strong>of</strong> canbe given in syntactically different ways, so the whole pro<strong>of</strong>, i.e. derivation+ interpretation + soundness pro<strong>of</strong>, is not a syntactic object. Moreover, thepart <strong>of</strong> the pro<strong>of</strong> which really is a syntactic object, the formal derivation,need not consist solely <strong>of</strong> sentences; it can consist <strong>of</strong> diagrams, as Miller’sexample shows.The visual thinking in this example consists in going through a sequence <strong>of</strong>diagrams and at each step seeing that the next diagram results from a permittedalteration <strong>of</strong> the previous diagram. It is a non-superfluous part <strong>of</strong> the process<strong>of</strong> thinking through a pro<strong>of</strong> that on any straight line segment an equilateraltriangle is constructible. It is clear too that in a process that counts as thinkingthrough this pro<strong>of</strong>, the visual thinking is not replaceable by non-diagrammaticthinking. That knocks out (b), leaving only (c): some thinking that involves adiagram in thinking through a pro<strong>of</strong> is neither superfluous nor replaceable bynon-diagrammatic thinking.This is not an isolated example. In the 1990s Barwise led a programmeaimed at the development <strong>of</strong> formal systems <strong>of</strong> reasoning using diagrams andestablishing their soundness. There was renewed interested in Peirce’s graphicalsystems for propositional and quantifier logic, and systems employing Eulerdiagrams and Venn diagrams were developed and investigated, culminating inthe work <strong>of</strong> Sun-Joo Shin (1994). Barwise was interested in systems which bettermodel how we reason than these, and to this end he turned his attention toheterogeneous systems, systems deploying both formulas and diagrams: he andEtchemendy developed such a system for teaching logic, Hyperpro<strong>of</strong>, andbeganto investigate its metalogical properties (Barwise and Etchemendy, 1996b). Thiswas part <strong>of</strong> a surge <strong>of</strong> research interest in the use <strong>of</strong> diagrams, encompassing

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!