13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

430 alasdair urquhartin his mathematical autobiography, Laurent Schwartz, who was eventually t<strong>of</strong>ind the generally accepted interpretation <strong>of</strong> the delta function as a distribution,remarks:I believe I heard <strong>of</strong> the Dirac function for the first time in my second year atthe ENS. I remember taking a course, together with my friend Marrot, whichabsolutely disgusted us, but it is true that those formulas were so crazy from themathematical point <strong>of</strong> view that there was simply no question <strong>of</strong> accepting them.(Schwartz, 2001, p.218)This attitude is logically impeccable, but it fails to account for the success thatthe physicists attained with their weird ideas. In other words, it is fruitless andunhelpful.There is a second attitude, also <strong>of</strong> an extreme type, that consists in saying—‘Well,there’s a contradiction, so what? As long as it works, that is all thatmatters’. This is close to the physicists’ own attitudes, since physicists are quitehappy to perform purely formal calculations as long as something resemblingthe right answer comes out in the end. I would also consider the idea <strong>of</strong>paraconsistent logic to be somewhat along the same line. Although the idea <strong>of</strong>a true contradiction perhaps makes some kind <strong>of</strong> sense, the idea on the wholedoes not appear to be very fruitful.The third attitude, which I might call the philosophical, or critical attitude,consists in a more nuanced approach to these scandalous invasions <strong>of</strong> themathematical universe. The idea here is, on the one hand, to maintain theview that the physicists’ calculations are largely correct, but that the objectsthey think they are talking about are in fact <strong>of</strong> a different nature.Out <strong>of</strong> this third, or critical, attitude, applied to the case <strong>of</strong> the Dirac deltafunction, comes the modern and very fruitful theory <strong>of</strong> distributions <strong>of</strong> LaurentSchwartz. It’s interesting to see what this move consists in. The idea here is thatthe Dirac delta function is not a function at all, but a distribution, thatistosay,a linear operator on a certain class <strong>of</strong> functions (the similarity <strong>of</strong> the strategyfollowed here to that <strong>of</strong> Rota’s in the case <strong>of</strong> the umbral calculus is quitestriking). The reason this works is that the delta function, as used by physicists,only appears in a certain restricted type <strong>of</strong> computation, and it is possibleto redefine this computation using the operators so that all <strong>of</strong> the physicists’calculations become perfectly rigorous. In this way, the mathematicians canenjoy the best <strong>of</strong> both worlds.Incidentally, the introduction <strong>of</strong> infinitesimals makes possible the explication<strong>of</strong> the Dirac delta function in a different and perhaps more intuitive way.We simply define a Dirac delta function as a function with a unit integral,all <strong>of</strong> whose mass is concentrated within an infinitesimal neighbourhood <strong>of</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!