13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

diagram-based geometric practice 77ancient diagram-handling practice, eventually perhaps to the point where wecan settle the original question about PP.3. The role <strong>of</strong> diagram use in ancient geometric analysis is highly non-trivial,and 20th-century discussions have shed little light on this. Compared to whatwe find in the Elements, ancient analytic practice (Pappus’ Collectio IV, VII)seems much less affected by case distinctions; probably due to matters <strong>of</strong> logicalorder (Behboud (1994)) as well as to the structuring <strong>of</strong> analytic reasoningby the collections <strong>of</strong> case-free what-determines-what lemmas such as Euclid’sData. Indeed, one as yet undescribed factor in geometrical analysis is thesense <strong>of</strong> what-determines-what that one only obtains by actually constructingdiagrams. (Study <strong>of</strong> geometrical analysis must include the rich Islamic tradition,cf. Bergren and van Brummelen (2000).)4. The nature <strong>of</strong> geometricality. Descartes’ method in geometry is guided byalgebraic form rather than by a geometrical diagram, and its algebraic manipulationsare not intelligibly related to the original problem diagram—perhapsbecause a problem has the same equation as infinitely many others, whose diagramsneed not be at all similar to the one intended. This strikes many authors,notably Leibniz, as a lack <strong>of</strong> geometricality; motivating two centuries <strong>of</strong> ultimatelyfruitful work to provide an ‘analysis situs’, some complementary theory<strong>of</strong> spatial arrangements that would respect geometrical form independent <strong>of</strong>the merely metric properties to which Descartes’ method reduces geometry.For example, Poncelet (1822) aims to regain diagrammatic intelligibility <strong>of</strong>geometrical reasoning while selectively maintaining uniform treatment <strong>of</strong> variantdiagrams achieved by algebraic methods. Via a system <strong>of</strong> reinterpretationsguided by algebra and continuous variation <strong>of</strong> diagrams, invoking complex(‘imaginary’) and ideal objects (‘at infinity’), he grounds a novel diagram readingpractice and an accompanying algebra <strong>of</strong> generalized line segments that togethereliminate case-branching even more than Descartes. (This is a clear case<strong>of</strong> enhanced uniformity <strong>of</strong> conception and argument that exploits standards <strong>of</strong>reasoning rather than choice <strong>of</strong> representation to suppress differential responseto certain different-looking diagrams.) At the same time, Poncelet’s diagrammaintains his grasp on a similarity class <strong>of</strong> Euclidean-individuated diagramsmuch narrower than those sharing a common Cartesian problem equation.ED and most other recent discussions cited address, in the spirit <strong>of</strong> logicalfoundations, primarily justificational roles <strong>of</strong> the geometrical diagram. Butdiagrams in Poncelet have lost some cogency roles that ED attributes themin Euclidean argument. Because <strong>of</strong> this, further contrasting Descartes’ ungeometricalgeometry with Poncelet’s (and Steiner’s) diagram use may helpbring out diagram contributions to geometricality that we have so far missedin looking at Euclid.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!