13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mathematics and physics: strategies <strong>of</strong> assimilation 425provide a consistent interpretation <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> the earlier calculations and pro<strong>of</strong>s.Indeed, this follows from the logic <strong>of</strong> the situation. Abraham Robinson (1966,Chapter X) argued strongly that his modern infinitesimal analysis could beseen as providing a retrospective justification for the procedures <strong>of</strong> Leibniz andhis followers. Nevertheless, historians <strong>of</strong> mathematics such as Bos (1974) havelooked askance at this attempt at assimilating Leibnizian methods to moderntechniques. However, some <strong>of</strong> Bos’s criticisms <strong>of</strong> Robinson involve absurdand impossible demands—for example, his first criticism (Bos, 1974, p.83) isthat Robinson proves the existence <strong>of</strong> his infinitesimals, whereas Leibniz doesnot! The fact remains—no interpretation <strong>of</strong> dubious and inconsistent practicesinherited from the past can be perfect in every respect. The most we can askis that a rigorous interpretation reproduce at least some <strong>of</strong> the most importantcalculations and concepts <strong>of</strong> the older technique.16.4 The umbral calculusThe example <strong>of</strong> infinitesimal calculus is rather intricate. To illustrate some<strong>of</strong> the basic methods <strong>of</strong> assimilation, we shall look at a simpler case, theumbral or symbolic calculus. This calculus first made its appearance as acomputational device for manipulating sequences <strong>of</strong> constants (Blissard, 1861);for the history <strong>of</strong> the method, see Bell (1938). Later, it was rediscoveredby the number theorist and inventor <strong>of</strong> mathematical games Lucas (1876).The self-taught engineer and theorist <strong>of</strong> electromagnetism, Oliver Heavisidedeveloped a similar operational calculus in the course <strong>of</strong> solving the differentialequations arising in the theory <strong>of</strong> electromagnetism. The famous analystEdmund T. Whittaker rated Heaviside’s operational calculus as one <strong>of</strong> thethree most important mathematical discoveries <strong>of</strong> the late 19th century.However, Heaviside’s work was regarded with distrust until Bromwich gave arigorous interpretation <strong>of</strong> Heaviside’s operators as contour integrals.All <strong>of</strong> these developments were regarded as somewhat questionable whenthey first appeared. To see why, let us use the example <strong>of</strong> the computation <strong>of</strong>the Bernoulli numbers B n in the umbral calculus. These numbers, <strong>of</strong> whichthe first few are as follows:B 0 = 1, B 1 =− 1 2 , B 2 = 1 6 , B 3 = 0, B 4 =− 1 30 , B 5 = 0, B 6 = 1 42 , ... ,play an important role in number theory and combinatorics. I claim they aredefined by the umbral equation: (B + 1) n = B n ,forn ≥ 2, together with the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!