13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 101The primary resource is a non-propositional acquaintance with control inexecuting constructions in a given diagram. The practice requires one to graspthat the attempt to connect two points by a straight line, for example, has nolegitimately competing alternate outcomes. In this attenuated and inarticulatesense, uniqueness is a part <strong>of</strong> what must be undertaken and subscribed to inPostulate 1. Little does it matter that Euclid might have asserted uniqueness,making it a propositional content <strong>of</strong> Postulate 1, by using some appropriateverbal form such as a definite article (as Mueller objects, p. 32), but did notdo so. Just so, one is required to grasp that the control one exercises inattempting to make the circles in the construction <strong>of</strong> I.1 is such that we shouldtake precisely two intersection points to arise as seen from the diagrams weproduce. At this level, there is no need <strong>of</strong> I.7 or III.10 (as Heath envisages,p. 261) to establish the uniqueness <strong>of</strong> the triangle in I.1. Such a requirement<strong>of</strong> non-propositional grasp is <strong>of</strong> course compatible with the lack <strong>of</strong> explicitlyarticulated concern with uniqueness which Mueller observes in Euclid.¹⁸In spite <strong>of</strong> this non-propositional grasp, challenges arise to what ‘justhappens’ in making diagrams. Perhaps the realm <strong>of</strong> non-propositional graspis a fool’s paradise? As constructions pile up, adequate grasp <strong>of</strong> what controlmay be exerted through proper diagram discipline may be unattainable forparticipants. For example, the two possibilities in I.1 could each lead to multipleand dissimilar possibilities in further constructions. What possibilities arise inthis way will typically depend on the initial data. It helps that, as one can nowestablish by metatheoretical means, a determinate construction has at mostfinitely many outcomes; each corresponding to an in principle independentlyintelligible geometrical condition on initial data.But also, the conditions on initial data under which various possibilities ariseneed not be open to grasp in carrying out the construction in a particulardiagram: in the all-triangles-are-isoceles argument, what clearly happens forclearly non-isoceles triangles might inscrutably cease to occur for certainclose-to-isoceles triangles; perhaps with some unimagined threshold. Wemay therefore need to survey the possible outcomes at each stage. Undersuch circumstances, a secondary resource in the practice comes to the fore:propositionally explicit claims and demonstrations concerning the outcome <strong>of</strong>¹⁸ The expectation <strong>of</strong> control in constructions is illustrated, for example, by a remark <strong>of</strong> Newton:he compares the traditional geometrical neusis construction <strong>of</strong> the conchoid with a regulation Cartesianconstruction <strong>of</strong> solutions to its cubic locus equation (pointwise by intersecting a varying circle andfixed hyperbola), and comments ‘... this [Cartesian] Solution is too compounded to serve for anyparticular Uses. It is a bare Speculation, and geometrical Speculations have just as much Elegancyas Simplicity, and deserve just so much praise as they can promise Use.’ (Universal Arithmetic 1728pp. 229–230.)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!