13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6 paolo mancosuphilosophers <strong>of</strong> mathematics and traditional epistemologists and ontologists <strong>of</strong>mathematics felt that the ‘mavericks’ were throwing away the baby with thebathwater.Within the traditional background <strong>of</strong> analytic philosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics,and abstracting from Kitcher’s case, the most important direction in connectionto mathematical practice is that represented by Maddy’s naturalism. Roughly,one could see in Quine’s critique <strong>of</strong> the analytic/synthetic distinction adecisive step for considering mathematics methodologically on a par withnatural science. This is especially clear in a letter to Woodger, written in1942, where Quine comments on the consequences brought about by his (andTarski’s) refusal to accept the Carnapian distinction between the analytic andthe synthetic. Quine wrote:Last year logic throve. Carnap, Tarski and I had many vigorous sessions together,joined also, in the first semester, by Russell. Mostly it was a matter <strong>of</strong> Tarski andme against Carnap, to this effect. (a) C[arnap]’s pr<strong>of</strong>essedly fundamental cleavagebetween the analytic and the synthetic is an empty phrase (cf. my ‘‘Truth byconvention’’), and (b) consequently the concepts <strong>of</strong> logic and mathematics are asdeserving <strong>of</strong> an empiricist or positivistic critique as are those <strong>of</strong> physics. (quotedin <strong>Mancosu</strong> (2005); my emphasis)The spin Quine gave to the empiricist critique <strong>of</strong> logic and mathematicsin the early 1940s was that <strong>of</strong> probing how far one could push a nominalisticconception <strong>of</strong> mathematics. But Quine was also conscious <strong>of</strong> the limits <strong>of</strong>nominalism and was led, reluctantly, to accept a form <strong>of</strong> Platonism based onthe indispensability, in the natural sciences, <strong>of</strong> quantifying over some <strong>of</strong> theabstract entities <strong>of</strong> mathematics (see <strong>Mancosu</strong> (Forthcoming) for an account <strong>of</strong>Quine’s nominalistic engagement).However, Quine’s attention to mathematics was always directed at itslogical structure and he showed no particular interest in other aspects <strong>of</strong>mathematical practice. Still, there were other ways to pursue the possibilitiesthat Quine’s teachings had opened. In Section 3 <strong>of</strong> this introduction I willdiscuss the consequences Maddy has drawn from the Quinean position. Letme mention as an aside that the analogy between mathematics and physics wasalso something that emerged from thinkers who were completely opposed tological empiricism or Quinean empiricism, most notably Gödel. We will seehow Maddy combines both the influence <strong>of</strong> Quine and Gödel. Her case is <strong>of</strong>interest, for her work (unlike that <strong>of</strong> the ‘mavericks’) originates from an activeengagement with the foundationalist tradition in set theory.The general spirit <strong>of</strong> the tradition originating from Lakatos as well asMaddy’s naturalism requires extensive attention to mathematical practice. Thisis not to say that classical foundational programs were removed from such

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!