13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

266 jamie tappendenfunctions ...) The upshot <strong>of</strong> the general investigation is a collection <strong>of</strong> generaltheories regarded by mathematicians (and hobbyists) <strong>of</strong> a range <strong>of</strong> differentbackgrounds and subspecialties as explaining the astonishing connection betweenarbitrary odd primes. The judgement that the Legendre symbol carves at ajoint interacts with a delicate range <strong>of</strong> mathematical facts and judgements:verified conjectures, the practice <strong>of</strong> seeking explanations and understanding,efforts to resolve more general versions <strong>of</strong> known truths (and the evaluations<strong>of</strong> ‘proper’ generalizations that support this practice), judgements <strong>of</strong> similarityand difference, judgements about what facts would be antecedently expected(quadratic reciprocity not among them), and more.The history <strong>of</strong> quadratic reciprocity also illustrates the importance <strong>of</strong>inductive reasoning in mathematics. Euler conjectured the law decadesbefore Gauss proved it, on the basis <strong>of</strong> enumerative induction from cases.²²This issue will be revisited in the research article, so I’ll just notethe key point.²³ In many cases, the natural/artificial distinction is linkedto projectibility: Natural properties (‘green’) support correct predictions andartificial ones (‘grue’) don’t. It is common, as in the influential work <strong>of</strong>Sydney Shoemaker (1980a, b), to connect this with a thesis about causality.Simplifying Shoemaker’s picture drastically: natural properties are those thatenter into causal relations, and it is because <strong>of</strong> this that only natural propertiessupport induction properly. Euler and quadratic reciprocity reveal alimit to this analysis: induction, as a pattern <strong>of</strong> reasoning, does not dependfor its correctness on physical causation. The properties supporting Euler’scorrect inductive reasoning have the same claim to naturalness deriving fromprojectibility that ‘green’ has. This is consistent with the observation thatmathematical properties don’t participate in causation as Shoemaker understandsit. Even though there is much more about inductive reasoning inmathematics that we need to understand better, and we should have dueregard for the differences between mathematical and empirical judgements,we shouldn’t underestimate the affinities.Delicate issues <strong>of</strong> identity and difference <strong>of</strong> content also arise, as in Dedekind’spro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> quadratic reciprocity in (Dedekind, 1877/1996). Dedekind describeshimself as presenting ‘essentially the same as the celebrated sixth pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>Gauss’ (from Gauss, 1817). The derivation recasts the treatment <strong>of</strong> cyclotomicextensions in section 356 <strong>of</strong> (Gauss, 1801). Dedekind is plausibly describedas presenting the same argument in a conceptual form avoiding most <strong>of</strong> the²² Edwards (1983), Cox (1989, pp. 9–20), and Weil (1984) are excellent treatments <strong>of</strong> the inductivereasoning that led Euler to his conjecture. There is a particularly beginner-friendly discussion at theonline Euler archive .²³ For more on plausible reasoning in mathematics see Jeremy Avigad’s first article.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!