13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 105a practice falls short <strong>of</strong> such capacity elsewhere, in a finite-to-one fashion: aswhen a geometrical assertion or argument admits <strong>of</strong> finitely many cases.The capacity for uniformity in diagram-based reasoning is limited bythe dependence <strong>of</strong> geometrical demonstration on what we have called itsappearance or topology—inclusions and contiguities <strong>of</strong> regions, segments, andpoints in the diagram. A geometrical pro<strong>of</strong> typically responds to the appearance<strong>of</strong> its diagram. If, in varying a diagram, ‘a line or a point has passed from the rightto the left <strong>of</strong> another’, as Poncelet puts it, we would need to reconsider whethersome region or inclusion invoked in the pro<strong>of</strong> might have disappeared. Theall-triangles-are-isoceles argument shows that such considerations as whethera point lies on one or the other side <strong>of</strong> a given line are crucial; if differentialresponsiveness to such conditions were allowed to relax, disarray is a virtualcertainty.Geometric text is typically more flexible, giving the appearance <strong>of</strong> greateruniformity <strong>of</strong> presentation than can be attained in a diagram-based demonstration.In the case <strong>of</strong> Apollonius, the resources <strong>of</strong> geometric text allowuniformity <strong>of</strong> formulation ultimately 87-fold beyond what geometric argumentrequires.As one would expect from a practice which engages its artifacts in thatway, topologically distinct diagrams are treated in separate argument; whereas—maximizinguniformity in artifact use—separate argument is inappropriatefor diagrams with the same appearance, however otherwise dissimilar. We willrefer to this as the ‘one appearance–one diagram’ principle. In this way, theartifact strategy <strong>of</strong> the practice, combining diagram and discursive text, attainsa ‘local optimum’ in making more manageable the diversity <strong>of</strong> spatial forms:by reducing it while retaining an important inferential grip.Euclidean geometry <strong>of</strong>ten prefers to avoid making case distinctions at theoutset <strong>of</strong> a pro<strong>of</strong>: the resources <strong>of</strong> geometric text allow one instead to substitutea formulation in which the appearance <strong>of</strong> diagrams is more fully described.Thus, a claim (p → q), where diagrammatically, p is one <strong>of</strong> p 1 or p 2 , wouldtend to be replaced by separate discursive claims (p 1 → q) and (p 2 → q).Indeed, under some circumstances, separate claims are required: constructionproblems <strong>of</strong>ten have preconditions <strong>of</strong> possibility (diorismoi), which must bestated as assumptions <strong>of</strong> a claim; these preconditions are <strong>of</strong>ten different fordifferent diagram topologies. The claim must then be made separately for suchdifferent diagram types.In other circumstances, case distinctions arise only within geometrical demonstrationand so are not readily avoidable. Arguments by reductio <strong>of</strong>ten require acase distinction because <strong>of</strong> trichotomy: when two quantities can be compared,the first is either greater, equal, or less than the second. If, for reductio,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!