13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

mathematics and physics: strategies <strong>of</strong> assimilation 419picture. Most <strong>of</strong> Cartier’s paper is devoted to showing how some <strong>of</strong> the mostoutrageous claims <strong>of</strong> Leonard Euler and other formally inclined mathematicianscan be given a sensible interpretation, even such crazy-looking assertions as‘∞! = √ 2π’ (Cartier, 2000, p.64). Similarly, Atiyah and Thurston, thoughdeclaring themselves in opposition to the attitudes <strong>of</strong> Jaffe and Quinn, whichthey see as overly restrictive and authoritarian, do not really disagree with themon the question <strong>of</strong> separating rigorously established results from mathematicalspeculation. Thus Atiyah remarks: ‘I find myself agreeing with much <strong>of</strong> thedetail <strong>of</strong> the Jaffe–Quinn argument, especially the importance <strong>of</strong> distinguishingbetween results based on rigorous pro<strong>of</strong>s and those which have a heuristicbasis’ (Atiyah et al., 1994, p.1), and Thurston says: ‘I am not advocating anyweakening <strong>of</strong> our community standard <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>; I am trying to describe howthe process really works. Careful pro<strong>of</strong>s that will stand up to scrutiny are veryimportant’ (Thurston, 1994, p.9).Nevertheless, it is clear that the debate reflects some major changes takingplace in the field <strong>of</strong> mathematics, changes that are reflected in the concludingremarks <strong>of</strong> Cartier in a 1997 interview with Marjorie Senechal:When I began in mathematics the main task <strong>of</strong> a mathematician was to bringorder and make a synthesis <strong>of</strong> existing material, to create what Thomas Kuhncalled normal science. Mathematics, in the forties and fifties, was undergoing whatKuhn calls a solidification period. In a given science there are times when youhave to take all the existing material and create a unified terminology, unifiedstandards, and train people in a unified style. The purpose <strong>of</strong> mathematics, in thefifties and sixties, was that, to create a new era <strong>of</strong> normal science. Now we areagain at the beginning <strong>of</strong> a new revolution. Mathematics is undergoing majorchanges. We don’t know exactly where it will go. It is not yet time to make asynthesis <strong>of</strong> all these things—maybe in twenty or thirty years it will be time fora new Bourbaki. I consider myself very fortunate to have had two lives, a life <strong>of</strong>normal science and a life <strong>of</strong> scientific revolution. (Senechal, 1998)It is clear that mathematics, after a period <strong>of</strong> inner consolidation andabstraction, is now open to influences on many sides, and the resultingopening-up induces anxieties on numerous issues. One <strong>of</strong> the anxieties relatesto the classification <strong>of</strong> researchers as mathematicians. Benoit Mandelbrot clearlyconsiders himself to be a mathematician, but rails against the evil influence<strong>of</strong> Bourbaki, and the ‘typical members <strong>of</strong> the AMS,’ whom he stigmatizes as‘Charles mathematicians’ (since the AMS headquarters is on Charles Street,Providence, RI). According to Mandelbrot, Jaffe and Quinn propose to set upa police state within ‘Charles mathematics’, and a world cop beyond its borders(Atiyah et al., 1994, p.16). Charles mathematicians practice a sterile form <strong>of</strong>research, and were the bane <strong>of</strong> great creative figures such as Henri Poincaré

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!