13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

12 paolo mancosusentiments appear in the writings <strong>of</strong> many philosophers <strong>of</strong> mathematics who holdthat the goal <strong>of</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics is to account for mathematics as it ispracticed, not to recommend reform. (Maddy, 1997, p.161)Naturalism, in the Maddian sense, recognizes the autonomy <strong>of</strong> mathematicsfrom natural science. Maddy applies her naturalism to a methodological study <strong>of</strong>the considerations leading the mathematical community to the acceptance orrejection <strong>of</strong> various (set-theoretical) axioms. She envisages the formulation<strong>of</strong> ‘a naturalized model <strong>of</strong> practice’ (p. 193) that will provide ‘an accuratepicture <strong>of</strong> the actual justificatory practice <strong>of</strong> contemporary set theory andthat this justificatory structure is fully rational’ (pp. 193–4). The method willproceed by identifying the goals <strong>of</strong> a certain practice and by evaluating themethodology employed in that branch <strong>of</strong> mathematics (set theory, in Maddy’scase) in relation to those goals (p. 194). The naturalized model <strong>of</strong> practiceis both purified and amplified. It is purified in that it eliminates seeminglyirrelevant (i.e. philosophical) considerations in the dynamics <strong>of</strong> justification;and it is amplified in that the relevant factors are subjected to more preciseanalysis than what is given in the practice itself and they are also applied t<strong>of</strong>urther situations:Our naturalist then claims that this model accurately reflects the underlyingjustificatory structure <strong>of</strong> the practice, that is, that the material excised is trulyirrelevant, that the goals identified are among the actual goals <strong>of</strong> the practice (andthat the various goals interact as portrayed), and that the means-ends reasoningemployed is sound. If these claims are true, then the practice, in so far as itapproximates the naturalist’s model, is rational. (Maddy, 1997, p.197)Thus, using the example <strong>of</strong> the continuum hypothesis and other independentquestions in descriptive set theory, she goes on to explain how the goal <strong>of</strong>providing ‘a complete theory <strong>of</strong> sets <strong>of</strong> real numbers’ gives rational support tothe investigation <strong>of</strong> CH (and other questions in descriptive set theory). Thetools for such investigations will be mathematical and not philosophical. Whilea rational case for or against CH cannot be built out <strong>of</strong> the methodology thatMaddy distils from the practice, she provides a case against V = L (an axiomthat Quine supported).We need not delve into the details <strong>of</strong> Maddy’s analysis <strong>of</strong> her case studies andthe identification <strong>of</strong> several methodological principles, such as maximize andunify, that in her final analysis direct the practice <strong>of</strong> set theorists and constitutethe core <strong>of</strong> her case against V = L. Rather, let us take stock.Comparing Maddy’s approach to that <strong>of</strong> the ‘maverick’ tradition, we canremark that just as in the ‘maverick’ tradition, there is a shift in whatproblems Maddy sets out to investigate. While not denying that ontological

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!