13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

introduction 9consists in trying to dismantle the foundationalist filter. The second, the parsconstruens, provides philosophical analyses <strong>of</strong> a few case studies from mainstreammathematics <strong>of</strong> the last seventy years. His major case studies come from theinterplay between mathematics and computer science and from n-dimensionalalgebras and algebraic topology.The pars destruens shares with Lakatos and some <strong>of</strong> his followers a stronganti-logical and anti-foundational polemic. This has unfortunately damagedthe reception <strong>of</strong> Corfield’s book and has drawn attention away from the goodthings contained in it. It is not my intention here to address the significance<strong>of</strong> what Corfield calls the ‘foundationalist filter’ or to rebut the argumentsgiven by Corfield to dismantle it (on this see Bays (2004) andPaseau(2005)).Let me just mention that a very heated debate on this topic took place inOctober 2003 on the FOM (Foundations <strong>of</strong> Mathematics) email list. The parsdestruens in Corfield’s book is limited to some arguments in the introduction.Most <strong>of</strong> the book is devoted to showing by example, as it were, what aphilosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics could do and how it could expand the range <strong>of</strong>topics to be investigated. This new philosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics, a philosophy<strong>of</strong> ‘real mathematics’ aims at the following goals:Continuing Lakatos’ approach, researchers here believe that a philosophy <strong>of</strong>mathematics should concern itself with what leading mathematicians <strong>of</strong> theirday have achieved, how their styles <strong>of</strong> reasoning evolve, how they justify thecourse along which they steer their programmes, what constitute obstacles totheir programmes, how they come to view a domain as worthy <strong>of</strong> study andhow their ideas shape and are shaped by the concerns <strong>of</strong> physicists and otherscientists. (p. 10)This opens up a large program which pursues, among other things, thedialectical nature <strong>of</strong> mathematical developments, the logic <strong>of</strong> discovery inmathematics, the applicability <strong>of</strong> mathematics to the natural sciences, thenature <strong>of</strong> mathematical modeling, and what accounts for the fruitfulness <strong>of</strong>certain concepts in mathematics.More precisely, here is a list <strong>of</strong> topics that motivate large chunks <strong>of</strong> Corfield’sbook:1) Why are some mathematical entities important, natural, and fruitful whileothers are not?2) What accounts for the connectivity <strong>of</strong> mathematics? How is it thatconcepts developed in one part <strong>of</strong> mathematics suddenly turn out to beconnected to apparently unrelated concepts in other areas?3) Why are computer pro<strong>of</strong>s unable to provide the sort <strong>of</strong> understanding atwhich mathematicians aim?

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!