13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

purity <strong>of</strong> method in hilbert’s grundlagen 241same breath with another, namely that, given a straight line and a circle inthe same plane, if the line has both a point in the interior <strong>of</strong> the circle anda point outside it, then it must intersect it, and in exactly two points.⁴¹ Callthis the line-circle property. Similar to this is what can be called the circle-circleproperty, namely a circle with points both inside and outside another circle hasexactly two points <strong>of</strong> intersection with it.⁴² The connection to the TriangleInequality Theorem is not surprising, for the circle-circle property is preciselywhat Euclid implicitly relies on in the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> I, 22.It is important to see Hilbert’s question as one concerning ‘purity <strong>of</strong> method’.It is well known that similar questions arise with the very first proposition <strong>of</strong>Euclid’s Elements (I, 1) which shows how to construct an equilateral triangleon a given base AB. Euclid’s construction takes the two circles whose centresare the endpoints <strong>of</strong> the base and whose radii are equal to the base; either <strong>of</strong>the two points <strong>of</strong> intersection <strong>of</strong> the circles can be taken as the third apex, C.But do the circles actually intersect? A standard objection is that there is noguarantee <strong>of</strong> this. Heath notes:It is a commonplace that Euclid has no right to assume, without premissing somepostulate, that the two circles will meet in a point C. To supply what is wantedwe must invoke the Principle <strong>of</strong> Continuity. (Heath, 1925, Volume 1, p.242)And by a ‘Principle <strong>of</strong> Continuity’, Heath means something like Dedekindcontinuity (op. cit., pp. 237–238). Heath also cites one <strong>of</strong> Hilbert’s contemporaries,Killing, as invoking continuity to show the line-circle property (Killing,1898, p.43). And many commentators on Euclid (for example, Simson in the1700s) raised this point with respect to the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Triangle InequalityProperty, while at the same time stating that it is ‘obvious’ that the circlesintersect, and that Euclid was right not to make any explicit assumption. WhatHilbert investigates is what formal property <strong>of</strong> space corresponds to the implicitunderlying existence/construction assumption.Hilbert constructs a model <strong>of</strong> his geometry (i.e. Axiom Groups I–III)in which the existence assumption fails, and where the Triangle InequalityTheorem (Euclid’s I, 22) also fails. Thus, the necessary conditions for Hilbert’spro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Three Chord Theorem are not present in a geometry based solelyon I–III. Moreover, since the Euclidean pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> I, 22 is based on a simplestraightedge and compass construction, Hilbert’s result is tantamount to sayingthat his axiom system does not have enough existential ‘weight’ to match thisparticular construction. This result is interesting, because, beginning with an⁴¹ Note that this has to be assumed for the power <strong>of</strong> point to be defined for all points and all circles.⁴² For similar properties, see pp. 62, 65 <strong>of</strong> Hilbert’s lecture notes, and pp. 63–64 <strong>of</strong> the Ausarbeitung,i.e. Hallett and Majer (2004, 335–337).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!