13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

purity as an ideal <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> 191advantage is enhanced if a solution is given in terms <strong>of</strong> concepts most familiarto her, and that (iii) the purer the pro<strong>of</strong> the more it conforms to this type <strong>of</strong>solution. Viewed this way, purity is a pragmatic virtue, albeit one which servesepistemic ends (namely, the effective utilization <strong>of</strong> knowledge to produce moreknowledge). It does not itself constitute an epistemic virtue; a pure pro<strong>of</strong> isnot, sheerly by dint <strong>of</strong> its purity, a better justification <strong>of</strong> the theorem it proves.It is, however, a more effective instrument for gaining further knowledge.We see here, then, a suggestion <strong>of</strong> the idea that purity generally increases theeffectiveness <strong>of</strong> divisions <strong>of</strong> epistemic labor based on specialization.²²Purity is thus a common concern among combinatorialists. It is not, however,unique to them. Indeed, it extends across a wide range <strong>of</strong> mathematical fields,and has been <strong>of</strong> concern both to researchers and educators throughout the20th century.A simple illustration is the search for a pure pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Erdös–Mordelltheorem. (Let ABC be a triangle and P be a point in its interior. Constructperpendiculars from P to each <strong>of</strong> the sides, letting the points <strong>of</strong> intersectionbe A ′ , B ′ , C ′ , respectively. The Erdös–Mordell theorem says that PA + PB +PC ≥ 2(PA ′ + PB ′ + PC ′ ).) Finding an elementary pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> this theorem wasa going concern in the middle decades <strong>of</strong> the 20th century, one that ended insuccess in the late 1950s (cf. Kazarin<strong>of</strong>f, 1957; Bank<strong>of</strong>f, 1958).Still other examples include Formanek (1973), Edmonds (1986), Gilmer andMott (1971), and Woo (1971). The first gives a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> a theorem <strong>of</strong> algebra(the Eakin–Nagata theorem) the virtue <strong>of</strong> which is said to be that it uses onlydefinitions <strong>of</strong> terms contained in the theorem.²³ The second presents a purelytopological pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> a topological theorem and, like the case <strong>of</strong> Stanton andZeilberger mentioned above, it expresses the hope that such a pro<strong>of</strong> will makethe theorem more ‘accessible’ to specialists.The third concerns a theorem first proved by Abraham Robinson usingmodel-theoretic methods. This theorem, though algebraic in character, was saidby Robinson not to have an accessible purely mathematical pro<strong>of</strong> independent<strong>of</strong> his model-theoretic approach. The authors challenge this by providing apurely algebraic pro<strong>of</strong>.²⁴I mention this because it points to a larger concern regarding purity,namely, whether pure pro<strong>of</strong>s always exist. This question, in turn, points to²² Recall here the remark <strong>of</strong> Bolzano’s (from Bolzano, 1804, 172) quoted in Section 2 concerningthe advantages <strong>of</strong> purity not only for purposes <strong>of</strong> making education more thorough but <strong>of</strong> making iteasier and more efficient.²³ The theorem states that if T is a commutative Noetherian ring finitely generated as a moduleover a subring R, thenR is also Noetherian.²⁴ See Friberg (1973, 421) for a different example concerning algebraic purity.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!