13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

130 kenneth manderswe sought to attribute rules to the practice which would account for this.Having recognized several rings <strong>of</strong> defense against error and indecisiveness,we find that remaining threats to geometry fail to motivate further discernablemeasures; indeed, fail to motivate the major actions <strong>of</strong> the practice.This embarrassment results from too severe a restriction <strong>of</strong> philosophicalfocus, by which we have deprived ourselves <strong>of</strong> an explanatory perspective ongeometrical diagram and pro<strong>of</strong>. We have looked at inferential roles, demonstration,and probing alike, exclusively as defense against error, unreliability, ordisagreement. This leaves us scarcely able to motivate why Euclid proves whathis diagram shows!Drawing on our broader perspective on intellectual practices as means <strong>of</strong>control, however, we can overcome this restriction <strong>of</strong> focus. For justificationby no means exhausts the control intellectual practices aspire to. To admit thatsomething just happens when we construct a chord in a circle, for example,that a particular region just pops up inside another one, is to admit defeat alonga broad front. In their disdain for ‘empirical geometry’ or ‘mechanical curves’,participants in the geometrical tradition express revulsion for such impotence.This sensation that confronts us when something ‘just happens’ in a diagrammay be contrasted with (a) the diverse measures that if taken may enhanceour control; (b) the diverse questions, to which the ability to answer is part <strong>of</strong>being in control; and also (c) the diverse virtues we recognize when we aremore in control.Starting with measures: guided by the diagram, we can (as in III.2 as aresponse to the chord location inside a circle) probe variant diagrams by way<strong>of</strong> case and objection, and seek claims and arguments to clarify the originaldiagram.For another example, we might have gone on our way to I.20, startingfrom circling two segments around the two endpoints <strong>of</strong> another segmentand noticing a triangle pop up when we draw lines from the intersection tothe two endpoints. This brute occurrence could then be probed by trying toget it to fail. If we stretch the base segment but not the others, we can seewhat happens to the intersection point; this could lead to the diorism <strong>of</strong> I.20.We could, however, apply the challenge to the construction <strong>of</strong> a triangle inthis way in the demonstration <strong>of</strong> I.1, reported by Proclus: the straight linesfrom the circle intersection to the ends <strong>of</strong> the base might have a commonsegment, and so not give a triangle with the given segments we circled aroundas upstanding sides. Or we might give the diagram <strong>of</strong> I.7 and object to theimplicit assumption <strong>of</strong> diagram control in the uniqueness <strong>of</strong> the outcome <strong>of</strong> theconstruction. Plainly, the brute diagram occurrence we started with does notcall forth a unique challenge; and although the initial diagram (and, perhaps,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!