13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

102 kenneth mandersconstructions. Examples would be uniqueness results such as I.7, orargumentsusing circumcircle and Simson-line to determine the appearance <strong>of</strong> the alltriangles-are-isocelesdiagram (Dubnov or Maxwell, pp. 24–25). Arguments <strong>of</strong>this sort shift part <strong>of</strong> the burden <strong>of</strong> grasp <strong>of</strong> construction outcomes, from what‘just happens’ in making diagrams with proper discipline (purely diagram-based)to a mixture <strong>of</strong> diagram- and discursive text-based moves.Of course, geometrical constructions are in general only quasi-determinate:adding elements to a diagram by a prescribed construction may yield finitelymany diagrams from any given initial diagram, rather than just one; as inthe two circle intersections in I.1. Instead <strong>of</strong> proving uniqueness, the taskin settling a theoretical question (such as whether all triangles are isoceles)becomes to determine all diagrams that have standing as the result <strong>of</strong> theconstructions indicated; and verify that they have the properties claimed <strong>of</strong>the construction. Moreover, it is understood that metrically different initialdiagrams with the same appearance may lead, via the same construction, todifferent finite collections <strong>of</strong> result-diagrams. (We will return to this.)In the example at hand, however, the question involves properties <strong>of</strong> theinitial diagram only: whether the given triangle is isoceles. It is then intolerable,whether or not the auxiliary constructions are unique in the ordinary sense,as they are here, that after their application to one and the same initial diagram,one result-diagram leads to a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the claim and another to its dispro<strong>of</strong>.Because the claim considered involves attributions to the initial diagram only,conflicting conclusions (that the triangle is both isoceles and non-isoceles) fromdistinct outcomes <strong>of</strong> the constructions indicated, applied to the same initialdiagram, would—except in a reductio context—put singular pressure indeedon any sense that geometric property attribution behaves like a truth predicate(or assertability): holds indifferently <strong>of</strong> the wider context <strong>of</strong> the objects <strong>of</strong>the claim.Until somehow relieved, such a situation would constitute an extremeform <strong>of</strong> disarray; quite distinct from that which one would encounter ifunable to resolve which <strong>of</strong> two diagrams would be the outcome <strong>of</strong> oneway <strong>of</strong> carrying out the construction, and the two potential outcomes led toconflicting conclusions on the main claim: then one would just not have apro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> either conclusion, perhaps a disconcerting situation but a thoroughlyfamiliar one. Indeed, if what looked to us all along as properties <strong>of</strong> a diagramwere instead implicitly relational qualities with respect to the wider context<strong>of</strong> the objects <strong>of</strong> the claim, this would undercut one <strong>of</strong> the key contributions<strong>of</strong> the discursive text in geometrical practice: it mediates application relationsbetween geometrical arguments, indifferent both to how the configurationto which the lemma applies is embedded in a diagram in the application,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!