13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

172 johannes hafner and paolo mancosuhow stringency should be weighted against the other criteria, size <strong>of</strong> conclusionset and size <strong>of</strong> the basis, it is impossible to incorporate the stringency criterioninto the determination <strong>of</strong> the best systematization <strong>of</strong> a given K. AtonepointKitcher even suggests that the notion <strong>of</strong> stringency could be clarified throughthe notions <strong>of</strong> explanation and unification (cf. Kitcher, 1981, p.519), thuscourting circularity. Due to all <strong>of</strong> these difficulties the stringency criterioncould not be employed in our discussion so far.The only context in which Kitcher actually puts to use the concept<strong>of</strong> stringency and formulates a workable requirement in terms <strong>of</strong> it is hisdiscussion <strong>of</strong> ‘spurious unifications’ which threaten to trivialize his account.The problem is posed by trivial yet maximally encompassing systematizations<strong>of</strong> our beliefs on the basis <strong>of</strong> single patterns like ‘from α&B infer α’ or,even more simple, ‘from α infer α’, where ‘α’ istobereplacedbyanysentence we accept. In order to exclude such patterns Kitcher invokes thecriterion <strong>of</strong> stringency. As he points out, the mentioned systematizations areindeed highly successful according to the criteria <strong>of</strong> generating a large number<strong>of</strong> beliefs on the basis <strong>of</strong> a small number <strong>of</strong> patterns but they fail badlyin terms <strong>of</strong> stringency. That is, ‘both <strong>of</strong> the above argument patterns arevery lax in allowing any vocabulary whatever to appear in the place <strong>of</strong> α’(Kitcher, 1981, p.527). Hence they are (intuitively) non-stringent and shouldbe excluded.Now, on the face <strong>of</strong> it, it might seem that a very similar case could be madeout against our systematization E I (K). To recall, E I (K) unifies the set K byusing the following single argument pattern, ‘TSP’ for short, which relies onthe Tarski–Seidenberg decision algorithm.(1) F(ϕ) = x(2) ψHere ‘ϕ’, ‘x’, and ‘ψ’ are dummy letters, whereas F denotes (some fixedspecification <strong>of</strong>) a decision algorithm for K.Filling instructions:Replace ‘ϕ’ byasentences in the language <strong>of</strong> RCF.Replace ‘x’ bythevalue,0or1,<strong>of</strong>F at s.Replace ‘ψ’ bys, ifF(s) = 1andreplace‘ψ’ by¬s, ifF(s) = 0Classification:Thesentence(1) isapremise.Thesentence(2) follows from (1) by metatheory, i.e. by using facts aboutthe functioning <strong>of</strong> F.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!