13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 127branching control is a relational matter. Given the statement <strong>of</strong> I.7, Proclus’alternative is a different-appearance diagram arising from different metricchoices (but not limitations on control in making the diagram from thosemetric choices) satisfying the verbal statement <strong>of</strong> hypothesis for reductio.Hence it is a case arising in the course <strong>of</strong> the argument, by our test <strong>of</strong> differentdegrees <strong>of</strong> uniformity in text and diagram. On the other hand, both diagramsin I.7 can be regarded as arising from appearance control probing; not in I.7but in earlier constructions such as that <strong>of</strong> I.1.4.6.3 Probing and knowledgeTraditional geometrical practice has no access, except through diagrammingand pro<strong>of</strong>, to ulterior standards <strong>of</strong> geometrical truth, by which it might back upits standards for handling text and diagram in demonstration. Not far under thesurface <strong>of</strong> Proclus’ frequent praise <strong>of</strong> the subtlety <strong>of</strong> Euclid’s formulations lieburied hosts <strong>of</strong> objections based on variant readings and earlier texts, objectionswhich are only avoided through what must long have seemed open-endedrefinement <strong>of</strong> expressive means and exploration <strong>of</strong> diagrammatic possibilities.Using diagrams is a much more effective strategy in gaining an intellectualgrip on space than we have been able to show here; but it does come at theprice <strong>of</strong> a certain open-endedness in geometrical reasoning: although ‘exact’conclusions are not read <strong>of</strong>f from the diagram, diagram use also remains inneed <strong>of</strong> probing, due to the limitations <strong>of</strong> diagram control.Because <strong>of</strong> this, the long-range stability <strong>of</strong> traditional geometry—acrosscenturies, participants, and the extended body <strong>of</strong> accumulated geometricalargument—cannot be understood without taking into account the constructivecritical attitude towards geometrical argument expressed through probing. Inour philosophical account <strong>of</strong> geometrical knowledge, probing must thereforeshare center stage with reasons.But if probing is conceptually central to traditional geometric practice, wecan no longer treat that practice as requiring unqualified assent to geometricclaims. Instead, geometrical practice must cultivate dissent in order to avoiddisarray! This dissent takes the form <strong>of</strong> vigorous critical scrutiny <strong>of</strong> geometricalargument. The normative structure <strong>of</strong> this dissent, however, differs from that<strong>of</strong> dissent in other practices, in which dissenting parties may stay clear <strong>of</strong>each other while they seek power (dissent in the body politic) or in whichthey may sometimes agree to disagree (dissent in the body philosophic). Thegeometer’s obligation is to assert (the protagonist), to probe, and to seek aresolution <strong>of</strong> differences; suited to stand up in that very process continued byother participants bound only by that same obligation. Taken all together, thisis a structure <strong>of</strong> unqualified responsibility, with the widest possible scope, for

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!