13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 103and to how the configuration to which the lemma applies is embeddedin a diagram enriched by constructions in the course <strong>of</strong> demonstration <strong>of</strong>the lemma.In view <strong>of</strong> the long record <strong>of</strong> entrenchment <strong>of</strong> the sense that geometricproperty attribution behaves like truth, as well as the central role <strong>of</strong> context-freeapplication relationships among the chain <strong>of</strong> propositions, it does not seem thatthis particular type <strong>of</strong> deep conflict has been widely felt to be in force for anynotable interval in the documented history <strong>of</strong> the practice. This may motivatewhat seems to be the standard <strong>of</strong> traditional geometrical practice for dealingwith the possibility <strong>of</strong> multiple outcomes <strong>of</strong> specified constructions on onegiven initial diagram: it suffices to treat one outcome (provided its standing assuch is not in question), leaving it to the process <strong>of</strong> probing (see later) whethersomething funny comes up when a different outcome diagram is considered.Perhaps this is best seen as a gamble, which serves to reduce quasi-uniquenessto effective uniqueness; together with an implicit acceptance <strong>of</strong> vulnerabilityto the underlying risk.The determinateness import <strong>of</strong> constructions is plainly not exhausted bytheir (quasi-) uniqueness (and existence) properties: the information that acertain construction, if properly carried out, will give a unique result neednot help in establishing what the metric properties or even appearance <strong>of</strong> theresult-diagram will be. Although extreme-sensitivity cases such as arbitrarilyclose-to-isoceles triangles may press constructional determinateness past itslimits, most diagram appearance issues are adequately dealt with by employingconstructions, subject to diagram discipline.4.3.3 Stipulative diagram controlA practice can resolve a limited number <strong>of</strong> artifact control problems bystipulation. Perhaps the Parallel Postulate should be understood to arise in thatway. As we vary the angle between two intersecting lines, we get a transition<strong>of</strong> behavior across the range <strong>of</strong> angles in which the intersection lies too faraway to draw. The intersection now lies to one side, ever farther out; butif we approach the same range <strong>of</strong> angles (for which the intersection lies to<strong>of</strong>ar away to draw) from the other side, the intersection lies to the other side,ever farther out. Because <strong>of</strong> this transition <strong>of</strong> behavior, something must besaid about the appearance <strong>of</strong> diagrams in this range; but precisely when theintersection lies too far away to draw, we have lost our diagramming artifactsupport: appearance control by diagram has been lost.With the benefit <strong>of</strong> hindsight, we can list some stipulations which couldbe made in this situation, compatibly with enough <strong>of</strong> traditional geometricalpractice to render the proposals competitors: (i) there is a single intersectionless,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!