13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

410 alasdair urquhartworld. However, this point <strong>of</strong> view brings with it considerable difficulties, thatare the fundamental subject <strong>of</strong> this chapter.The basic difficulty is this: if we construe these models simply as mathematicalobjects, then we have to face the fact that physicists do not employ normalmathematical methods in investigating them. Rather, the methods that theyuse are frequently so far from normal mathematical practice that it is sometimesnot clear that the objects themselves are even mathematically well defined.15.2 A renewal <strong>of</strong> vowsThroughout most <strong>of</strong> their history, mathematics and physics have been closelyintertwined, as can be seen by looking at the history <strong>of</strong> ancient astronomy(Neugebauer, 1975). Furthermore, if we look at work by mathematicians andphysicists from the early 19th century, the standards <strong>of</strong> mathematical rigourused by both groups <strong>of</strong> researchers appear indistinguishable. For example, CarlFriedrich Gauss has a high reputation among mathematicians for the rigour<strong>of</strong> his mathematical reasoning, but a glance at his famous treatise <strong>of</strong> 1827 ondifferential geometry (Gauss, 2005) shows that it makes free and uninhibiteduse <strong>of</strong> the infinitesimal quantities that later mathematicians were to regard withfear and loathing.The middle years <strong>of</strong> the 20th century saw an unprecedented divergencebetween the two communities <strong>of</strong> researchers. As Faddeev (2006)remarks,intheearlier part <strong>of</strong> this century, mathematical physics was not distinguished from theoreticalphysics—both Henri Poincaré and Albert Einstein were called mathematicalphysicists. However, with the expansion <strong>of</strong> theoretical physics in the1920sand1930s, a separation between the two areas occurred. Whereas ‘mathematicalphysics’ came to be understood as a somewhat restricted area, confinedto the study <strong>of</strong> mathematical techniques such as the solution <strong>of</strong> partial differentialequations and the calculus <strong>of</strong> variations, the theoretical physicists themselves,caught up in trying to understand the physics <strong>of</strong> atoms and elementary particles,began to move further and further away from the confines <strong>of</strong> mathematicalrigour. Although there are notable examples <strong>of</strong> interactions between mathematiciansand physicists in the middle part <strong>of</strong> the 20th century, such as theelucidation <strong>of</strong> quantum mechanics in terms <strong>of</strong> linear operators on Hilbert spaceand the application <strong>of</strong> fibre bundles to non-Abelian gauge theory, in general theconcepts and standards <strong>of</strong> the two fields showed an ever increasing divergence.The pressure <strong>of</strong> experimental results, notably the explosion <strong>of</strong> new elementaryparticles discovered during the 1950s and1960s, forced theoretical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!