13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

188 michael detlefsenPurity was thus widely accepted as an ideal <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> in 19th centurymathematics. This notwithstanding, it was not without its detractors. Theseincluded such eminences as Hilbert and Klein. Hilbert viewed purity as a‘subjective’ ideal (cf. Hilbert, 1899, 106–107).¹⁸ The important thing, he said,is that we learn as much as we can about the different means by which a giventheorem or body <strong>of</strong> theorems can be proved. Pure pro<strong>of</strong>s—that is, pro<strong>of</strong>sthat concern themselves only with the concepts contained in the theoremsproved—are therefore part <strong>of</strong> what we want to know. They are, however,only part and are not inherently more interesting or valuable than pro<strong>of</strong>s thatdraw upon other conceptual resources.Klein believed that much <strong>of</strong> mathematics, including much <strong>of</strong> analysis,ought in many instances to be confirmed by geometrical intuition. In addition,he believed that without ‘constant use’ <strong>of</strong> geometrical intuition thepro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the most interesting and important analytic results concerningcontinuity would be impossible, at least practically speaking (cf. Klein,1894, 45).He also challenged purity in the other direction. That is, he proposed asystem <strong>of</strong> axioms for geometry that made use <strong>of</strong> analytic ideas and methods,and, generally speaking, he recommended this system for its efficiency. At thesame time, he decried the resistance <strong>of</strong> geometers to this simple approach, aresistance he also attributed to traditional ideas <strong>of</strong> purity, in this case thoseembodied in the retrograde refusal to use numbers in geometry (cf. Klein,1925, 160).Promoting efficiency as a more compelling ideal than purity was hardly a newattitude, however. It was, indeed, at the core <strong>of</strong> 17th, 18th, and 19th centurydebates concerning the use <strong>of</strong> algebra in geometry (cf. Wallis, 1685, 117–118,305–306;MacLaurin,1742, 37–50) and, relatedly, the division <strong>of</strong> mathematicalreasoning into methods <strong>of</strong> discovery and methods <strong>of</strong> demonstration.7.3 Purity as a contemporary idealPurity has thus come into conflict with other ideals <strong>of</strong> mathematical reasoning,conflicts which, at best, have been only partially resolved. This unresolved¹⁸ The subdivision <strong>of</strong> axioms in Hilbert’s Grundlagen bespeaks a moderate concern for purity, andone that’s reflected in the larger organization <strong>of</strong> the book. Thus, for example, Ch. I, §4 is entitled‘Consequences <strong>of</strong> the axioms <strong>of</strong> incidence and order’ and Ch. I, §6 ‘Consequences <strong>of</strong> the axioms <strong>of</strong>congruence’. His intention, he said, was to deduce the most important theorems in such a way as tobring to light ‘the meaning <strong>of</strong> the various groups <strong>of</strong> axioms, as well as the significance <strong>of</strong> the conclusionsthat can be drawn from the individual axioms’ (Hilbert, 1899, 2).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!