13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

34 marcus giaquintoPythagoras’s theorem is used to infer that the base <strong>of</strong> the right-angled trianglehas length √ ab,wherea and b are the diameters <strong>of</strong> the larger and smaller <strong>of</strong> theosculating circles respectively; then visualizing what happens to the trianglewhen the diameter <strong>of</strong> the smaller circle varies between 0 and the diameter <strong>of</strong>the larger circle, one infers that √ ab (a + b)/2andthat √ ab = (a + b)/2justwhen a = b. Reflecting on this way <strong>of</strong> reaching the inequality one can retrievethe premisses and the steps, and by expressing them in sentences construct asound non-visual argument. This is quite different from the visual genesis <strong>of</strong>our belief that the triangles <strong>of</strong> a square either side <strong>of</strong> a diagonal are congruent.In that case reflection on our thinking does not provide us with any argument,and we are reduced to saying ‘It’s obvious!’In some cases visual thinking inclines one to believe something but onlyon the basis <strong>of</strong> assumptions suggested by the visual representation that remainto be justified given the subject’s current knowledge. In such cases there isalways the danger that the subject takes the visual representation to show thecorrectness <strong>of</strong> the assumptions and ends up with an unwarranted belief. Insuch a case, even if the belief is true, the subject has not discovered the truth,as the means <strong>of</strong> belief-acquisition is not reliable and demands <strong>of</strong> rationalityhave been transgressed. This can be illustrated by means <strong>of</strong> an example takenfrom Nelsen’s Pro<strong>of</strong> Without Words (Montuchi and Page, 1988) presentedinFig. 1.5.Reflection on this can incline one to think that when the positive realnumber values <strong>of</strong> x and y are constrained to satisfy the equation x.y = k (wherek is a constant), the positive real number values <strong>of</strong> x and y for which x + y isminimal are x = √ k = y. (Let ‘#’ denote this claim.) Suppose that a personknows the conventions for representing functions by graphs in a Cartesiancoordinate system, and knows also that the diagonal represents the functiony = x, and that a line segment with gradient −1from(0, b) to (b, 0) represents(0, j)xy = k(0, 2 k)(k,k)(2k, 0)(j, 0)Fig. 1.5.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!