13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 113What would not work well is a reductio argument starting with aninarticulate denial <strong>of</strong> a diagram: ‘Things are not like this’; in logical terms, adiagram-based reductio pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> (D 1 &... &D m ), starting with ¬(D 1 &... &D m ).(Of course, there might be such a reductio argument entirely within theresources <strong>of</strong> the discursive text.) In diagram-based reasoning, reductio gets itsgrip only when it leads determinately to a diagram.4.5.3 Further constraints on the diagram for reductio: I.27Our text <strong>of</strong> Euclid does not fully conform to the account given so far. I.27considers the straight line EF falling on two straight lines AB, CD such thatthe alternate angles AEF, EFD are equal (Fig. 4.6); and then assumes forreductio, and without loss <strong>of</strong> generality, that AB and CD produced meet inthe direction <strong>of</strong> B, D,atG. The diagram in the text would be read as subjectedto the equality <strong>of</strong> alternate angles with EF, which <strong>of</strong> course precludes straightlines from meeting a short distance away at G. Thus, the diagram gives up onsubjecting AB and CD produced to being straight, in order to indicate theirintersection at G. (So far, so good.)We moderns might indicate this intersection by producing either or bothAB and CD free-form monotonically curved toward their intersection G.Thiswould allow one to attribute the triangle GEF referred to later in Euclid’sargument (the requisite straightness <strong>of</strong> GE and GF is indicated in the text eventhough the diagram is not subjected to it). Admittedly, ancient practice doesnot appear to have utilized free-form curves; but instead apparently sought tosatisfy the requirements <strong>of</strong> argument by a diagram somehow made up fromthe ordinary types <strong>of</strong> diagram elements. This desideratum can be satisfiedfor any <strong>of</strong> the proposals just made, however, by substituting a circular arcfor free-form curves. In his diagram for an objection to I.4 (239), ProclusAEBGCFDAEBGFig. 4.6.CFD

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!