13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

purity <strong>of</strong> method in hilbert’s grundlagen 203mathematics’, and partly explain therefore his interest in purity questions.But it would be misleading to suggest that Hilbert regards ‘purity’ questionsas merely heuristic in this way, at least judging by his foundational work ongeometry, which Hilbert took to be the paradigm <strong>of</strong> foundational analysis.Purity <strong>of</strong> method investigations, in so far as they concern not just openproblems but also the analysis <strong>of</strong> the sources <strong>of</strong> mathematical knowledge,was fundamentally important to Hilbert. But to understand exactly how, itis necessary to recognize the novelty <strong>of</strong> Hilbert’s approach to foundationalissues, and to see the considerable effect this had on the type <strong>of</strong> mathematicalknowledge obtained through a purity investigation. There is a sense inwhich mixture <strong>of</strong> mathematical domains is intrinsic to Hilbert’s investigations;on the one hand, higher-level mathematics is essential to foundationalinvestigation <strong>of</strong> theories, even relatively low-level ones, and this higher levelalso instructs the fundamental source <strong>of</strong> geometrical knowledge. On theother hand, the examples given in Sections 8.4.1–8.4.3 make it clear that,while ‘purity’ results do throw light on on the question <strong>of</strong> the appropriatesources <strong>of</strong> knowledge for geometry, parallel to this are abstract mathematical/logicalresults at what Hilbert calls the ‘conceptual level’. Not only doesthis level largely emancipate mathematics from the epistemological constraints<strong>of</strong> the ‘appropriate’, but it is an essential part <strong>of</strong> what is attained by a‘purity’ result. But there is a twist, which we will consider at the end inSection 8.5.8.2 The foundational projectBefore we go further, it is worth pointing out a number <strong>of</strong> things aboutHilbert’s approach to geometry.In the first place, Hilbert’s axiomatic presentation as it appeared in theGrundlagen <strong>of</strong> 1899 (and, to some extent, the preceding lectures) builds on thetradition <strong>of</strong> synthetic geometry, a tradition which saw a strong revival throughthe work <strong>of</strong> Monge and von Staudt in the middle <strong>of</strong> the 19th century. Inparticular, Hilbert attempted to avoid where possible the direct intrusion <strong>of</strong>numerical elements. Underlying this, at least in part, was a view that geometryis <strong>of</strong> empirical and intuitive origin, and concerns ‘the properties <strong>of</strong> things inspace’.⁶ This is concisely summarized in Hilbert’s introduction to his 1891lectures on projective geometry:⁶ This view is what underlies the Vorlesungen <strong>of</strong> Pasch from 1882. It is, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>of</strong> much olderprovenance.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!