13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mathematical concepts: fruitfulness and naturalness 291predicted ones? And further down the road: if the conjecture is resolved by apro<strong>of</strong>, will it be proven true or false?Of course, the Euler case is unusual, in that elementary enumerative induction<strong>of</strong> the form ‘a 1 is P, a 2 is, P, ... , a n is P, therefore a n+1 will be P’ isasrare in mathematics as it is in ordinary reasoning about the physical world:both ordinary and mathematical conjectures are typically more subtle.⁹ Inboth empirical and mathematical cases, the simple enumerative induction is anartificially simplified touchstone that distills certain essential features <strong>of</strong> moreformless kinds <strong>of</strong> prediction and conjecture that inform ongoing mathematicaland empirical thinking.The practice <strong>of</strong> conjecturing and then striving to ascertain whether ornot the conjecture is correct is ubiquitous in mathematical practice.¹⁰ Evenwithout the formality <strong>of</strong> explicitly announcing a conjecture, the practice <strong>of</strong>forming expectations about what will turn out to be correct, grounded in priordiscoveries, is an indispensable component <strong>of</strong> mathematical reasoning. Theseexpectations guide the choice <strong>of</strong> directions to search for pro<strong>of</strong>s, for example.The concepts that are marked out as mathematically natural support furtherinductive practice: on the basis <strong>of</strong> similarities that are evaluated using theseconcepts, conjectures are made about what further investigations will discover.If it is discoved that these conjectures are true, it reinforces the judgementthat the concepts regarded as mathematically natural really are mathematicallynatural. In at least some cases the expectations are sufficiently well-grounded incomputations or other quasi-empirical data or plausibility considerations thatit seems right to say that the theorems are known to be true even without apro<strong>of</strong>. (This seems to be a reasonable thing to say about Euler’s justified beliefin quadratic reciprocity, for example.)Inductive reasoning doesn’t just appear in the direct form <strong>of</strong> conjecturesor specific expectations that are then ideally refuted or verified. Broadermethodological virtues like ‘significance’ and ‘fruitfulness’ have a kind <strong>of</strong>quasi-empirical inductive character.¹¹ Singling out a property as central tacitlymakes a prediction that it will reappear in unexpected contexts, and serve as⁹ Though there are significant examples in which an approach is initially validated through itsability to make verifiable predictions. Perhaps the most famous is the Schubert calculus for countingintersections <strong>of</strong> curves. Long before the system could be rigorously formulated and demonstrated,Schubert was making astonishing predictions <strong>of</strong> intersection numbers. See Kleiman and Laksov (1972).¹⁰ A good recent discussion <strong>of</strong> conjecture as an aspect <strong>of</strong> mathematical reasoning is in Mazur (1997).The classic investigations <strong>of</strong> inductive reasoning in mathematics are <strong>of</strong> course Pólya (1968) andLakatós(1976). Putnam (1975) is an illuminating reflection on the philosophical angles. Corfield (2003,Chapters2–6) contains some valuable discussion.¹¹ ‘Quasi-empirical’ is the expression coined by Hilary Putnam for this sort <strong>of</strong> mathematical evidentialsupport in his ‘What is <strong>Mathematical</strong> Truth?’ (Putnam, 1975).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!