07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

133<br />

and his refutation of the three traditional proofs of God. There is a<br />

similarity in structure between the arguments raised against these ideas in<br />

those early texts and the ones found in the Transcendental Dialectic of<br />

the Critique, he argues. He also notes that at an early stage Kant was<br />

putting forward the idea that mathematics is a synthetic discipline.<br />

Hartmut und Gernot Böhme, pointing at the fact that Kant’s critical<br />

perspective involves a reflection on the relation between our cognitive<br />

powers and the objects of our experience, maintain that such a<br />

perspective is present already in 1766 in Dreams of a spirit-seer. 7<br />

Kaulbach recognizes a critical attitude as early as 1747 in Kant’s first<br />

publication. Kant here critically distinguishes between Erkenntniszielen,<br />

Kaulbach claims, and by doing this anticipates the critical examinations<br />

of the Critique. 8 As we have seen in an earlier chapter, Rossvær also<br />

contends that Kant’s Copernican perspective is first advanced in<br />

Directions in space from 1768. 9<br />

Such examples all serve to undermine the idea of an absolute dividing<br />

line between the critical project of the 1770s and 1780s and the<br />

preceding period. On a general level this point has also been put forward<br />

by Schönfeld who contends that there is more continuity in Kant’s<br />

philosophizing than appears at first sight. Contrary to what Kant himself<br />

claims in the Critique, 10 Schönfeld argues, the inception of the critical<br />

philosophy was not an abrupt conceptual breakthrough, but rather a<br />

series of incremental steps that began with Kant’s growing<br />

disenchantment with the pre-critical project in the 1760s. 11 Scott-Taggart<br />

denounces the contrast between Kant’s pre-critical and critical views as<br />

‘an exegetical fiction’. 12<br />

Even if I shall not evaluate these various claims about continuity in<br />

detail here, I am generally sympathetic towards the idea that there is a<br />

continuity in Kant’s intellectual development in the way that ideas and<br />

perspectives central to the Critique are found in texts published both<br />

before and after it. I am also sympathetic towards those who argue that<br />

our understanding of the Critique is enhanced by interpreting it in the<br />

context of these other writings. Trying to understand a text in its context<br />

is, I think, always a profitable interpretative strategy, and where the<br />

7<br />

Böhme and Böhme (1983), 253.<br />

8<br />

Kaulbach (1960), 68.<br />

9<br />

Rossvær (1974), 43.<br />

10 Cf. B xvi and B xxii.<br />

11<br />

Schönfeld (2000), 7.<br />

12<br />

Scott-Taggart (1969), 3.<br />

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!