07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

SPATIAL EXPERIENCE <strong>AND</strong> THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE 157<br />

interpreted as referring to a mind that is thoroughly embodied, meaning,<br />

amongst other things, that both its domain of activity and its domain of<br />

immediate awareness are congruent with that of the body. Secondly, I<br />

claim that what in the Critique is abstractly described as ‘affection’ (the<br />

term is not further defined) is to be understood as the affection of the<br />

body, or better, the embodied self. Kant’s theory of affection is relevant<br />

to the present discussion because it is part of his critical theory of<br />

sensibility, forming the context within which his critical notion of space is<br />

first explored. Finally, I claim that Kant’s critical theory of space, in<br />

which space is defined as the form of intuition and the claim is advanced<br />

that this form originates in the activity of the mind, should be read as a<br />

theory of how our experience of space is constituted through embodied<br />

acts and practices.<br />

Even if I stress the similarities between Kant’s two theories of space<br />

here, I do not claim that they are similar in all respects. Kant’s theory of<br />

space, as found in the Critique, is both more complex and more<br />

sophisticated than the theory of space found in or implied by other<br />

Kantian texts. In the Critique we find highly sophisticated arguments,<br />

ideas and perspectives that are found nowhere outside it, or if they are<br />

found, only as fragments or suggestions. Nowhere except in the Critique<br />

are these arguments, ideas and perspectives presented as part of a unified<br />

and comprehensive theory. But when we turn our attention to some<br />

essential features of the basic structure of his critical theory of space,<br />

these are the same as those we find in his embodied theory of space. In<br />

this sense the former theory may be regarded as the abstract version of<br />

the latter. This is what I am going to argue below.<br />

The idea that Kant’s critical theory of space contains implicit<br />

references to the body in some of the ways suggested above has also been<br />

put forward by others. 2<br />

In an argument similar to mine, Kaulbach points<br />

to the connection between Kant’s theory of space in Directions in space<br />

and Orientation, where our experience of space is claimed to be<br />

grounded in the awareness of embodied movement, and Kant’s critical<br />

theory of space. Even if Kant does not explicitly say so, we have to<br />

conceive of the human self of the Critique as an embodied self, Kaulbach<br />

contends, and as such, as inhabiting the same spatio-temporal world as<br />

the things of its experience. 3 Moreover, as a spatial being it has no means<br />

of experiencing the spatiality of this world other than by moving around<br />

2 Cf. e.g. Falkenstein (1995), Kaulbach (1960, 1965 and 1968), Rossvær (1974),<br />

Melnick (1989), Saugstad (1992) and Wyller (2000), cf. especially p. 162.<br />

3 Kaulbach (1965), 150.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!