07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE<br />

135<br />

pragmatic perspective of his anthropology is from now on to form a<br />

superior perspective under which he wants to subordinate his whole<br />

academic enterprise. Exactly what this says about the relation between<br />

his anthropology and his transcendental philosophy is not evident.<br />

Brandt argues that there are no systematic relations between these two<br />

branches of his philosophy, 15<br />

while Pitte, Munzel and others insist that<br />

there are, citing as evidence, for instance, the passage from the Logic<br />

quoted at the beginning of this chapter. 16 Munzel argues specifically that<br />

there is a connection between Kant’s anthropology and pedagogy and his<br />

critical ethics as found in the Critique of practical reason. In his<br />

anthropology and pedagogy Kant discusses the means and strategies by<br />

which man realizes his true vocation as a citizen of the moral world<br />

order. The second Critique, she maintains, cannot be properly<br />

understood in abstraction from these means and strategies. 17<br />

I will argue that a parallel argument may also be advanced where the<br />

first Critique is concerned, i.e., its cognitive theory, epistemology and<br />

transcendental idealism. This I also take to be the basic intuition<br />

underlying Pitte’s attempt at a positive re-evaluation of Kant’s<br />

anthropology. 18 However, like Munzel he ends up emphasizing the<br />

connection between Kant’s anthropology and his critical ethics, and does<br />

not quite succeed in integrating other parts of Kant’s transcendental<br />

philosophy into his interpretative approach. 19<br />

His position may at best be<br />

described as ambiguous. For instance, at one point he claims that Kant’s<br />

critical analysis of cognition provides little occasion for the introduction<br />

of anthropological elements. 20 In his introduction to an English<br />

translation of Kant’s Anthropology, however, he argues that Kant’s<br />

theory of cognition, as we find it in this work, may also help us to better<br />

15<br />

Brandt (1999), 50.<br />

16<br />

Pitte (1971 and 1978), Munzel (1999).<br />

17<br />

Cf. Munzel (1999), 8ff. Recently other scholars have also developed a similar<br />

perspective. For a brief survey, cf. Zammito (2002), 347ff. Zammito himself<br />

seems also to be sympathetic towards this view.<br />

18<br />

Cf. Pitte (1971), 32.<br />

19<br />

Referring to the last part of the Critique, and interpreting the text as a whole in<br />

the light of this part, Pitte argues that its orientation is basically practical (Pitte<br />

(1971), 33). From this Pitte further concludes that Kant intended the Critique to<br />

be a part of a comprehensive philosophy, the aim of which was to help realize the<br />

good life for the human race (Pitte 1971), 36. Within this system, Pitte argues,<br />

Kant considered his ethics to be the highest discipline.<br />

20<br />

Pitte (1971), 32.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!