07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

260<br />

We may now proceed to another of the objections suggested above.<br />

The categories are classified as concepts. According to our traditional<br />

understanding of what a concept is, however, it is not an embodied<br />

practice. How are we to solve this problem? A first step towards a<br />

solution may be found by reminding ourselves that the term ‘concept’<br />

may have several meanings. Sometimes it is used to mean ‘mental<br />

representation’. At other times, it may refer to a system of beliefs, or<br />

prototypes. 27 Johannessen complains that philosophers typically use the<br />

term as if it were settled what it meant, when it is not. 28<br />

In some Kantian texts published before and after the Critique we<br />

have seen that Kant promotes what we have called a pragmatic theory of<br />

embodied rationality, according to which a person may possess a concept<br />

solely through the successful performance of an embodied practice. In<br />

such a case, the concept exists in the practice itself, or as what we termed<br />

a working concept. In this and the following sections I shall examine<br />

some statements in the Critique about the categories. I shall argue that<br />

even if Kant does not explicitly say that the categories are embodied<br />

practices, what he says is consistent with the idea that they are such<br />

practices.<br />

Notice how Kant typically qualifies the categories. They are functions<br />

or acts carried out by the agent, or as Kant puts it in German, they are<br />

Handlungen des reinen Denkens (A 57/B 81). However, the categories<br />

are also referred to as rules. 29 A category, we may conclude, is both an act<br />

and a rule, or an act taking place according to a rule. This way of<br />

paraphrasing the point conforms to Kant’s definition of a practice, so at a<br />

general level his way of describing the categories conforms to his own<br />

definition of a practice. It may be objected that the parallel is merely<br />

formal here, and should not be emphasized too much. I agree, but the<br />

Critique also contains other interesting reflections on the connection<br />

between concepts, categories and practices. Not surprisingly, given what<br />

we have previously learned from examining his Logic, they are found in<br />

Kant’s general discussion of logic introducing the second main part of the<br />

Critique, the Transcendental logic.<br />

27<br />

Cf. Peacocke (1992), 3.<br />

28<br />

Cf. Johannessen (1999), 95.<br />

29<br />

Cf. e.g. A 126 and B 145.<br />

<strong>KANT</strong>’S TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!