07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> SPACE<br />

Above I argued that, according to the theory of Rousseau, Tetens<br />

and the other authors examined at the beginning of this chapter, touch is<br />

not only taken to be essential because it is the sense by which our first<br />

and most basic concepts of space are formed but it is also taken to be<br />

essential in being the sense on which the functioning of all the other<br />

senses is modeled. I think that the last example examined may be used as<br />

evidence that Kant’s thoughts on the matter followed the same lines, at<br />

least where hearing is concerned. In hearing, we do not touch objects<br />

directly, but in Kant’s analysis what happens is structurally similar to an<br />

act of touching. When I touch an object with my hand, this is an active<br />

movement. The resulting concept of the spatial form of the object is in<br />

part caused by this movement. However, just as important as my own<br />

movement is the resistance offered by the object. Without this resistance,<br />

I should not be able to form a concept of its form.<br />

The structure of this event, I think, is also present in the example of<br />

the blind person. Standing in the room, not knowing where its walls are,<br />

he uses his voice, and by noting how it is echoed by the room’s walls, he<br />

understands where they are relative to himself. What is the structure of<br />

this event? First the blind person acts by making a sound with his voice.<br />

Secondly, due to the resistance of the walls, this sound is reflected back to<br />

his ears. And once again the resulting concept of the spatial dimensions<br />

of the room is the result of both. Both the initial act and the resistance of<br />

the object, in this case the walls, are required.<br />

Metaphorically speaking, we might say that the sound in the above<br />

example is like a hand. By means of the sound, the observer reaches out<br />

for an object. When the sound hits the object, it is like the moment of<br />

touch, and the resistance causing the reflection of the sound is like the<br />

resistance felt when he literally touches an object, only now it is<br />

experienced indirectly, mediated by the sounds reflected back to his ear. I<br />

have found no evidence to suggest that Kant conceived of the act of<br />

seeing in an analogous way, but by arguing along the same lines as<br />

Descartes did in his example of the man with the sticks, he could well<br />

have extended the above model to include this sense as well.<br />

2.7 Summary<br />

In this chapter I have given a brief outline of what I have called Kant’s<br />

embodied theory of space and I have argued that this theory, at least in<br />

part, may be seen as inspired by authors such as Condillac, Tetens and<br />

Rousseau. However, I have also argued that it may be seen as the logical<br />

consequence of some basic Kantian ideas. If, for instance, we start out<br />

from the idea expressed explicitly both in Dreams of a spirit-seer and the<br />

77

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!