07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

152<br />

Critique, most of the proof is presented in a highly abstract language. He<br />

starts by stating that our experience presupposes that we think of<br />

substances as standing in dynamic, reciprocal relations. This is easily<br />

confirmed by experience, he claims. Had it not been for the dynamic<br />

relations of our world, we would never have been able to direct our<br />

senses from one object to another. So far, the style of the passage is<br />

abstract. The dynamic reciprocal relations under consideration are<br />

described as involving substances and our senses, but without specifying<br />

what these objects or senses are.<br />

Then it is as if the text moves to a completely different level. In the<br />

middle of a sentence, as if what follows is the most natural way of<br />

continuing, Kant starts to talk about eyes and light, and how the light<br />

plays between our eyes and the heavenly bodies. 80<br />

From our experiences it is easy to notice that only continuous<br />

influence in all places in space can lead our sense from one object to<br />

another, that the light that plays between our eyes and the heavenly<br />

bodies effects a mediate community between us and the latter and<br />

thereby proves the simultaneity of the latter, and that we cannot<br />

empirically alter any place (perceive this alteration) without matter<br />

everywhere making the perception of our position possible; and only<br />

by means of its reciprocal influence can it establish their simultaneity<br />

and thereby the coexistence of even the most distant objects (though<br />

only mediately). (A 213/B 260)<br />

What is remarkable in this passage is the ease with which it passes from<br />

the abstract level of transcendental discourse to the level of physical<br />

objects, and even more than this, how the subject or self who is all along<br />

abstractly present is suddenly disclosed as an embodied self with eyes and<br />

other organs. This ease more than suggests, I think, that this domain of<br />

physical objects and embodied selves is tacitly presupposed all the time as<br />

the obvious context in which the reflection proceeds.<br />

Another possible explanation, compatible with the first, of why the<br />

embodied aspect of human existence is not dealt with more explicitly in<br />

the Critique, is that Kant deliberately chose to keep this aspect in the<br />

background. Perhaps his conception of the ideal form of a philosophical<br />

work induced him to formulate his reflections in an abstract language in<br />

80<br />

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE<br />

The heavenly bodies, i.e the moon and the earth, were also mentioned some<br />

pages earlier at A 211/B 257.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!