07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> THE TRANSCENDENTAL 231<br />

example may be used to illuminate this relation in a Kantian sense. First,<br />

it illuminates what I take to be a central Kantian point, that moving from<br />

an empirical to a transcendental perspective does not mean that we<br />

suddenly become different people or that we deal with another world<br />

with other kinds of objects. The move involves a change in perspective<br />

only, focusing on our way of attaining experience of objects rather than<br />

the objects of this knowledge. This point, I think, is clearly expressed in<br />

the passage quoted at the beginning of this chapter:<br />

The difference between the transcendental and the empirical<br />

therefore belongs only to the critique of cognitions [Erkenntnisse] and<br />

does not concern their relation to their object. (A 57/B 81)<br />

The example also illustrates how our experience or knowledge of the<br />

ball, as we take it to exist within the empirical perspective, is grounded in<br />

our immediate awareness of our embodied states. It is not a free-floating<br />

image in a disembodied mind. Notice also how these states are of two<br />

sorts. First we have the awareness of our palms and fingers as they are<br />

affected by the texture of the ball. Then we have the awareness of our<br />

hands and perhaps the rest of the body as we actively grasp the ball and<br />

let our hands move along its surface. What within the empirical<br />

perspective we refer to as the texture of the ball corresponds to or is<br />

grounded in the first sort of awareness, while what within this perspective<br />

we refer to as its shape, corresponds to or is grounded in the second sort<br />

of awareness.<br />

Below I shall argue that the reflection presently entertained also<br />

entails the idea that space is transcendentally ideal, or at least that space<br />

may be described in the same terms as we find in the Kantian doctrine of<br />

the transcendental ideality of space. Before we reach that point, however,<br />

we need to return for a moment to the example of the ball. Imagine<br />

yourself again holding it in your hands with closed eyes. Imagine how<br />

you move your hands along its surface. When you consider the ball with<br />

the everyday confidence that characterizes what we have called the<br />

empirical perspective, the ball is simply there, in space, with a certain<br />

fixed shape, independently of whether you observe it or not. Thus its<br />

spatiality, i.e. shape, is what Kant calls empirically real. If, however, you<br />

direct your attention to that of which you are immediately aware only,<br />

the shape of the ball is not simply there anymore. What is there, is your<br />

awareness of that which in the perspective now established corresponds<br />

to the empirical shape of the ball. As we have seen above, and as is<br />

obvious from the example, this is the movement you are making with<br />

your hands as you move them along the surface of the ball.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!