07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

232<br />

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> THE TRANSCENDENTAL<br />

What is the relation between what within the first perspective is seen<br />

as the shape of the ball, and this awareness of movement? As long as you<br />

actually stand there examining the ball, I think there is a sense in which<br />

the two are the same. When you say to yourself that the ball is round,<br />

thereby making a statement belonging to the empirical perspective, there<br />

is a sense in which the term ‘round ball’ refers to your awareness of your<br />

movement. Now, please notice the implication of this: the spatial features<br />

of the ball, i.e. its shape, which inside the first perspective is seen as<br />

empirically real, and according to Kant legitimately so, must in a<br />

transcendental perspective be acknowledged as your awareness of your<br />

own movement. Transcendentally considered space not only presupposes<br />

embodied activity, space is such activity, or better, embodied, selfdetermined<br />

movement of which we are immediately aware.<br />

I have focused on an example in which the tactile sense is central not<br />

just because I think it is illuminating, but also because, as I have argued<br />

earlier, I take embodied acts such as the one explored in this example to<br />

be prototypical in Kant’s cognitive theory. In all perception there is an<br />

essential aspect of embodied movement. In visual perception, for<br />

instance, I typically move my pupils as their focus slides along the<br />

external contours of the object perceived. Consequently, I think the<br />

results just arrived at may be generalized to include all kinds of<br />

perception. Stated generally, and transcendentally considered, space is<br />

awareness of embodied movement, or better, it is embodied, selfdetermined<br />

movement of which we are immediately aware. 16<br />

We have now arrived at a position that is consistent with all the<br />

central ideas defining Kant’s doctrine of the transcendental ideality of<br />

space. In the Critique he contends that, transcendentally considered,<br />

space is subjective. 17 According to the present interpretation it is so<br />

because the notion of space, transcendentally considered, refers to the<br />

awareness of the embodied movements of the cognitive agent. It is also<br />

16<br />

I am here close to Kaulbach’s interpretation, cf. e.g. Kaulbach (1965), 104.<br />

Here he writes: ‘Die Lehre Kants von Raum und Zeit in der transzendentalen<br />

Ästhetik konnte den Begriff der Bewegung nicht voll entfalten, weil die beiden<br />

‘Formen’ der Anschauung hier noch isoliert von der Synthesis mit dem<br />

Verstande behandelt werden. Im weiteren Verlauf der Vernunftkritik zeigt sich<br />

jedoch immer deutlicher das Hervortreten des Bewegungsprinzips. Es wird dabei<br />

deutlich, daß Raum und Zeit nichts für sich sind, sondern Momente an dem<br />

Wesen der Bewegung: Beide müssen daher von ihr her philosophisch analysiert<br />

werden.’ I am also close to Melnick’s position (1989), 6 when he ascribes to Kant<br />

the view that space ‘is fundamentally our behavior or something we do’.<br />

17<br />

Cf. e.g. A 26/B 42. Cf. also A 99, A 103 and B 162.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!