07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

296<br />

CAUSALITY <strong>AND</strong> COMMON SENSE PHYSICS<br />

now use Piaget as a guide. More specifically, when we find a practice<br />

claimed by Piaget to have the same cognitive function as the relational<br />

categories have according to Kant, then we may argue that this practice<br />

is what we are looking for, i.e. it is where the category is present qua<br />

practice. In what follows, I shall do that.<br />

11.3 Sensorimotor practices and the relational categories<br />

In the first analogy Kant explains the fact that we think of the objects of<br />

our experience as permanent by referring to the category of substance.<br />

Thus the category of substance accounts for the fact that we ascribe to<br />

objects existence also in the periods when they are not immediately<br />

perceived. According to Piaget, the child shows it has a sensorimotor<br />

understanding of object-permanence when, for instance, it is found<br />

searching for an object, including when this object is not immediately<br />

perceived. Actually, according to Piaget, to entertain this and similar<br />

practices is what it means at this level to know that objects have a<br />

permanent existence. There is no knowledge of object-permanence<br />

independent of and external to these practices. This means that if we<br />

accept that there is a sense in which the child at this level experiences<br />

itself to be living in a world of permanent objects, this experience is made<br />

possible by the above suggested practices. The practices are a priori<br />

conditions for possible experience in this specific sense. Let us assume<br />

that all these practices are versions of one general practice, and let us call<br />

this ‘the practice of object-permanence’.<br />

The reason why I suggest that this general practice may be present in<br />

more than one version is that I do not want to confine attention only to<br />

those specified above, i.e. the practice of searching for an object,<br />

including when this object is not immediately perceived. Actually, I think<br />

that any act in which we adjust our behavior to the world of objects so<br />

that certain desired ends are produced and others are avoided may be<br />

seen as an example of the same general practice. An instance of this may<br />

be when the child grasps and explores an object. Thus, I think that an<br />

original, primitive sensorimotor knowledge of object-permanence is<br />

found when the child first learns to grasp a ball or another object placed<br />

before it.<br />

In an earlier chapter I used the example of a person exploring a ball<br />

to illuminate the idea that space is transcendentally ideal. Let us return to<br />

this example, however, and now imagine that the person in question is a<br />

child in the sensorimotor period. Let us also try to describe the event in<br />

Kantian terminology. Transcendentally considered, what we call the<br />

spatial shape of the ball is the awareness the child has of the movements

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!