07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

18<br />

THE EMBODIED M<strong>IN</strong>D<br />

early years are concerned, he is typically regarded either as a traditional<br />

metaphysician or as a philosopher of science, or both. Michael Friedman<br />

may be seen as representing the second view, in characterizing the young<br />

Kant as a committed and sophisticated Newtonian, who attempted to<br />

construct the philosophical underpinnings of the Principia. 15 Schönfeld<br />

presents a version of the first view by claiming that the underlying theme<br />

of Kant’s early philosophy was the attempt to reconcile natural science<br />

and metaphysics, or, more specifically, to help construct a unified, nondualist<br />

model of nature. Inside this model, the young Kant hoped it<br />

would be possible to harmonize Newtonian physics with the main<br />

assumptions of metaphysics, i.e. the presence of purpose in the world, the<br />

possibility of freedom, and the existence of God. 16<br />

Many views also prevail concerning which philosophers or traditions<br />

influenced the young Kant. There is a longstanding tradition within<br />

Kant scholarship of looking at the young Kant as a dogmatic follower of<br />

Leibniz. I think Tonelli is right, however, in claiming that even if he was<br />

influenced by Leibniz, at no point was he a dogmatic disciple of the great<br />

German philosopher. 17 Further, an overemphasis on Leibniz may easily<br />

overshadow the fact that Kant also oriented himself in other directions.<br />

Tonelli reports that when Kant started his philosophical career, Leibniz<br />

had for a long time been subject to the criticisms of the Pietist school of<br />

philosophers, of which Crusius was a distinguished member. Against the<br />

rationalism of Leibniz, Crusius argued that the domain of human<br />

knowledge was more limited than the rationalists assumed, a point Kant<br />

also adopted. And even if Kant never became an orthodox follower of<br />

Crusius, his early philosophy was clearly influenced by him. 18 Other<br />

influences included Hume, Locke, Reid, Tetens, Lambert, Condillac,<br />

Newton and Rousseau, to mention just a few. 19<br />

This variety of philosophers and thinkers to whom Kant related in<br />

the development of his own thoughts should alert us, I will argue, to their<br />

15<br />

Friedman (1992).<br />

16<br />

Schönfeld (2000), 10.<br />

17<br />

Tonelli (1969), LI.<br />

18<br />

For the influence of Crusius on Kant, cf. also Wundt (1924), 70.<br />

19<br />

Kant’s contemporary Ludwig Ernst Borowski reports that Kant was extensively<br />

concerned with Hume and Rousseau, cf. Gross (1993), 69. Rousseau’s influence<br />

is also emphasized by Pitte (1971), Cassirer (1981) and Zammito (2002). As for<br />

Kant’s relation to other thinkers, cf. also Beck (1969a), Vleeschauwer (1962),<br />

Kitcher (1990), Kuehn (2002), Schönfeld (2000), Vorländer (1977), Kaulbach<br />

(1982), and Beiser (1987).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!