07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SPATIAL SCHEMATISM 199<br />

states that in this case too some kind of embodied movement is necessary<br />

in order to recognize the triangle as a triangle, a movement similar in<br />

structure to the movement employed in the construction of a triangle.<br />

Does such a movement exist? If so, what could it be? One possible<br />

answer is that our eyes move as we observe the triangle. That is, in<br />

observing the triangle we let the focus of our eyes pass along its contours,<br />

and in doing this, our eyes make the required movement. The act may<br />

take place in less than a second and it may take place without explicit<br />

awareness, but nevertheless the movement is there. And again the<br />

movement is similar in structure to the one we would have used if we<br />

were to construct a triangle. 46 I take Kant’s point in the schematism<br />

chapter to be that we recognize a perceived triangle as a triangle when<br />

we see one, because this latter movement is the same in structure as the<br />

one we would have used to construct one, and that this similarity is<br />

noticed in the act of visual perception.<br />

From his reading of contemporary theories on visual perception,<br />

Kant was well aware that visual perception presupposes the movement of<br />

the eyes, or at least, this was what some of these theories claimed.<br />

Consequently there is nothing to prevent us from assuming that his<br />

theory of schematism can be interpreted as referring to such movements<br />

when applied to visual perception. Or perhaps we should use the term<br />

‘acts’ instead of ‘movements’, to emphasize that to Kant perception is<br />

something we actively perform, not just something we passively undergo.<br />

The same point may also be applied to the third example of the<br />

schematism chapter concerning the empirical representation of a dog.<br />

The concept of a dog signifies a rule in accordance with which my<br />

imagination can specify [verzeichnen] the shape of a four-footed<br />

animal in general, without being restricted to any single particular<br />

shape that experience offers me or any possible image that I can<br />

exhibit in concreto. (A 141/B 180)<br />

Interpreted according to the now established guidelines, we have here<br />

the concept of a dog, the schema of this concept, which is the method<br />

according to which an image of a dog is produced, and finally the image<br />

itself. Further, Kant uses the concept of drawing [verzeichnen] in order<br />

to describe the process of producing the form [Gestalt] of the dog.<br />

46<br />

Imagine, for instance, that the pupils of the observer sent out laser beams with<br />

the capacity to make marks in some background medium. Then the movements<br />

used to construct a triangle on this background would be the same as the ones<br />

made when the focus of the eyes passed along the contours of an existing triangle.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!