07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

248<br />

<strong>KANT</strong>’S TRANSCENDENTAL EPISTEMOLOGY<br />

Kant also argues that transcendental philosophy involves setting up a<br />

certain kind of proof structure. Not any a priori insight [Erkenntnis] is<br />

transcendental. Characteristic of a transcendental insight [Erkenntnis] is<br />

that it makes us understand that and how certain representations<br />

(intuitions or concepts) are possible and may be used a priori only.<br />

And here I make a remark the import of which extends to all of the<br />

following considerations, and that we must keep well in view, namely<br />

that not every a priori cognition must be called transcendental, but<br />

only that by means of which we cognize that and how certain<br />

representations (intuitions or concepts) are applied entirely a priori,<br />

or are possible (i.e., the possibility of cognition or its use a priori). (A<br />

56/B 80)<br />

In order to denote this transcendental proof structure, Kant introduces<br />

the notion of a transcendental deduction. Most familiar is the<br />

transcendental deductions of the categories. However, he also refers to<br />

the proof structure of the Transcendental aesthetic as a transcendental<br />

deduction (A 87/B 119-120). A transcendental deduction in general is<br />

compared with a trial (A 84/B 116). 5 The aim of this trial is to explain<br />

how it is possible for a concept to relate a priori to objects, and why this<br />

use of the concept is justified. A transcendental deduction is contrasted<br />

with an empirical deduction in which only the origin of the concept is<br />

explained (A 85/B 117).<br />

8.2 Problems<br />

As Kant’s transcendental epistemology is part of his transcendental<br />

philosophy, 6 what has been said so far also applies to this epistemology.<br />

This raises a number of problems relative to what I have set out to prove<br />

in this chapter, that the categories may be conceived of as embodied<br />

practices. The claim, for instance, that only pure a priori representations<br />

5<br />

For a highly interesting study of the etymology of the term ‘deduction’ and the<br />

meaning it had for Kant, cf. Dieter Henrich’s influential article (1989). According<br />

to Henrich, the meaning of the term for Kant cannot be identified narrowly with<br />

a logical deduction, represented by a syllogism, but was influenced by the<br />

juridical Deduktionsschriften of his time which aim it was to justify controversial<br />

legal claims, cf. Henrich (1989), 32.<br />

6<br />

The reason why I here distinguish between Kant’s transcendental philosophy in<br />

general and transcendental epistemology in particular is that I take Kant’s notion<br />

of transcendental philosophy to include more then just an epistemology. It<br />

includes, e.g. also his transcendental psychology, i.e., cognitive theory.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!