07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>AND</strong> THE TRANSCENDENTAL 215<br />

to which these forms do not apply. In making these claims one may easily<br />

get the impression that Kant is speaking from a point beyond the<br />

empirical world. The same applies to the transcendental theory by which<br />

he purports to explain how our representations of this empirical world<br />

are constituted. Although Kant maintains that there is no way in which<br />

we can escape our subjective forms of experience, nevertheless he seems<br />

to have discovered a method (in the form of a transcendental reflection)<br />

by which such a position may still be reached, a position from which we<br />

may explain transcendentally how our representations are constituted,<br />

without including in our explanation anything empirical.<br />

In this chapter I shall argue, however, that despite how it may seem,<br />

Kant’s transcendental idealism does not demand that we adopt an<br />

interpretation like this one. Another interpretation of this idealism is<br />

possible according to which we may both maintain all its basic doctrines<br />

and at the same time, without inconsistency, conceive of the cognitive<br />

agent of the Critique as embodied and the transcendental psychology<br />

associated with this agent as referring to embodied acts and events.<br />

Actually, I shall argue that Kant’s transcendental idealism follows from a<br />

line of reflection in which the embodied self and the embodied nature of<br />

human cognition are basic premises. Within the context of this<br />

interpretation, the idea of embodied cognition is not foreign to or<br />

inconsistent with Kant’s transcendental idealism. On the contrary,<br />

because it is a premise underlying transcendental idealism, in promoting<br />

this idealism Kant both accepts and presupposes that cognition is<br />

embodied.<br />

It may be argued that this strategy involves a vicious circularity. In<br />

order to defend the idea that the embodied mind has a central place<br />

within Kant’s transcendental philosophy I argue that transcendental<br />

idealism may be seen as the end product of a line of reflection taking as<br />

its starting point the idea that the human mind and human cognition is<br />

embodied. Thus I assume what is to be proved. However, I have already<br />

given independent arguments in support of the idea that the cognitive<br />

agent of the Critique is an embodied self and that its cognition is<br />

embodied. This is not an ad hoc hypothesis suddenly introduced at this<br />

point. Secondly, my immediate aim in this chapter is not to supply<br />

further proofs for this idea. My aim is more modestly to argue that it is<br />

not contradicted by Kant’s transcendental idealism, if only we<br />

understand it in the right way.<br />

The following discussion will touch upon topics that have been<br />

extensively discussed in Kant scholarship, such as the relation between<br />

empirical objects and things in themselves. I will reflect upon my position<br />

relative to this discussion towards the end of this chapter. First, however,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!