07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6<br />

<strong>IN</strong>TRODUCTION<br />

practice. This theory, I shall suggest, was developed in part inspired by<br />

Rousseau, who, I think, had a far more profound influence on Kant than<br />

most interpreters have acknowledged. In both Kant and Rousseau we<br />

find expressions of a deep respect for the skills and practices of the<br />

common artisan and everyday life. This, I suggest, is far more than just<br />

superficial admiration, but serves as the basis for revising the very<br />

concept of rationality.<br />

The first part of the present work deals with what I have found most<br />

significant in my reading of Kant’s early publications, as well as some<br />

works published after 1781, the year the Critique first appeared. I see this<br />

first part as an independent work that might have been published<br />

separately because it draws attention to some aspects of Kantian<br />

philosophy that, even if they are now receiving more attention than they<br />

used to, are still too little known within the general community of<br />

philosophers, let alone among the wider public. However, this first part is<br />

included in the present work because I think it also has an important role<br />

to play in understanding the context in which the Critique should be<br />

interpreted.<br />

That a work has to be interpreted in context, and that this should<br />

include what its author wrote at other times, is of course neither new nor<br />

foreign to interpreters of Kant. With a few exceptions, however, the<br />

works I explore in the first part of this work have not generally been<br />

regarded as really relevant to the Critique, and I think this has been<br />

detrimental to our understanding of it. Even if the Critique contains<br />

some philosophical reflections that have few if any parallels outside it, we<br />

also find strong continuities between the Critique and the works just<br />

referred to. A number of concepts with a central function in the Critique<br />

also appear in these other Kantian texts. More than one of the questions<br />

discussed in the Critique is also examined there. By including these texts<br />

in the context within which we interpret the Critique, therefore, we are<br />

in a better position to understand this central piece of Kantian<br />

philosophy than we would be if they were ignored.<br />

Finally, by reading the Critique in this context, we are able to<br />

respond to those who claim that the theoretical reflections of the Critique<br />

cannot be taken to refer to embodied events, skills or practices, because<br />

Kant did not care about the body, or that such reflections were foreign to<br />

the intellectual climate of the eighteenth century. By becoming<br />

acquainted with the writings discussed in part one of this work, we<br />

discover that Kant both could and did ascribe a basic significance to<br />

embodied events, skills and practices in his philosophy in a way that may<br />

seem radical even today. Reading the Critique in the context of these

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!