07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

210<br />

SPATIAL SCHEMATISM<br />

However, even if the Critique may contain the idea of such a<br />

primitive space, we are seriously misled if we believe we have now<br />

reached the core of Kant’s critical theory of space, because this theory<br />

aims much wider. Its task is to explain how it is possible for us to have<br />

knowledge of objects in space, and of the shape and the reciprocal<br />

relations of these objects. To know this, more is required than just to be<br />

affected by these objects, even if this affection has a spatial structure in<br />

the way that Falkenstein claims. What is required is activity: the cognitive<br />

agent has to be able to move. This is what I take to be Kant’s insight<br />

before, in and after the Critique. And when in the Critique he describes<br />

this activity with a terminology that seems to suggest that the activity in<br />

question is mental or internal, for example when he uses the term<br />

‘synthesis’, a further examination reveals that this is not the case after all.<br />

The acts referred to by the Kantian term synthesis also include embodied<br />

acts. 61<br />

Falkenstein fails to see this by uncritically adopting a far too narrow<br />

conception of the term ‘synthesis’, according to which the synthetic acts<br />

described in the Critique are purely intellectual acts whose main function<br />

is to unite material supplied by the senses, material that already has a<br />

temporal and spatial form. Thus, he conceives of even the figurative<br />

synthesis as intellectual. However, Kant classifies it as an imaginative<br />

synthesis, and if I am right, it corresponds to what Kant calls the<br />

syntheses of apprehension and reproduction. As I have argued, it needs<br />

to be conceived of as a constructive activity involving the body. With his<br />

far too narrow conception of synthesis, Falkenstein fails to see this point.<br />

6.14 The embodied agent<br />

According to Hans Blumenberg, most scientific and philosophical<br />

theories rest on a basic metaphor. 62<br />

The term ‘metaphor’ is here used in<br />

the sense of an image serving as a model from which the basic structure<br />

and concepts of the theory are derived, without, however, entering the<br />

field of abstract discourse itself, except through occasional references.<br />

The metaphor belongs to what I have called the background or horizon<br />

within which the more abstract theory is developed. 63<br />

Without intending<br />

to go deeply into this subject, I think that, in the Critique, the embodied<br />

agent is Kant’s basic metaphor in a Blumenbergian sense. An embodied<br />

61<br />

Cf. e.g. my discussion of the synthesis of apprehension.<br />

62<br />

Blumenberg (1960).<br />

63<br />

Cf. also Black (1962).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!