07.12.2012 Views

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

BODY AND PRACTICE IN KANT

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

SPATIAL EXPERIENCE <strong>AND</strong> THE <strong>BODY</strong> <strong>IN</strong> THE CRITIQUE 159<br />

examination will introduce us to concepts and perspectives central to the<br />

further discussion of my thesis.<br />

5.2 The architectonic of the Critique<br />

The first part of the Critique, the Transcendental doctrine of elements, is<br />

divided into two parts. The first part, the Transcendental aesthetic, is<br />

dedicated to a critical examination of sensibility. Within this context<br />

Kant gives a first basic introduction to his critical theory of space,<br />

according to which space is defined as a form of intuition. The second<br />

part, the Transcendental logic is also divided into two parts, the first of<br />

which is the Transcendental analytic, dedicated to Kant’s critical<br />

examination of the understanding. Here we also find the part of the<br />

Critique that has perhaps received more attention than any other, the socalled<br />

transcendental deductions of the categories or in short, the<br />

transcendental deductions. The Transcendental analytic also contains<br />

what is commonly referred to as Kant’s theory of schematism. The<br />

architectonic of the text suggests a neat division between the topics<br />

discussed: for a proper understanding of Kant’s critical theory of<br />

sensibility and space we only have to look at the Transcendental<br />

aesthetic. A closer inspection of the text, however, reveals that the matter<br />

is more complicated than this. Kant argues that in the constitution of<br />

human experience, sensibility and understanding never operate alone.<br />

Even if these two faculties of the mind may be distinguished<br />

conceptually, they always work together in an integrated way.<br />

My argument in this chapter is based on the assumption that in order<br />

to arrive at a thorough understanding of Kant’s critical theory of<br />

sensibility and space, one has to include not only what he says in the<br />

Transcendental aesthetic, but also what he says in the Transcendental<br />

analytic. Consequently, this chapter will examine parts of both, including<br />

the two versions of the transcendental deduction. 6 The literature on both<br />

the Transcendental aesthetic and the transcendental deductions is vast.<br />

As for the Transcendental aesthetic, the literature typically examines the<br />

various arguments Kant presents in order to prove the a priori character<br />

of time and space qua forms of intuition. As for the transcendental<br />

deductions, the focus is usually on their logical structure and how this<br />

6<br />

That the Transcendental aesthetic can only be understood properly in light of<br />

later parts of the Critique, is also argued by commentators like Rossvær (1974),<br />

100, Schaper (1992), 312, and Kaulbach (1965), 104.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!